Consciousness, Literature and the Arts
Archive
Volume 7 Number 3, December 2006
___________________________________________________________________
Benson,
Ophelia; Stangroom, Jeremy, Why Truth Matters, London, Continuum
International Publishing Group - Academi, 2006. 202 pages, ISBN
0-8264-7608-2, £12.99
Reviewed
by
Lund
University
The book under
review, Why Truth matters (WTM), closes yet another chapter of the prolific wave of literature
coming out of the ‘Truth Wars’. Authors
on both sides of the fence – the radical relativists or extreme sceptics and
their opponents – have assumed their respective roles as veritable crusaders.
As a result, their claims and counterclaims have come indeed in several forms
and guises. And these can vary significantly according to their style or degree
of seriousness and subtleness.
As you probably
surmised from the title, Benson and Stangroom’s WTM
opposes unqualified relativism and thus allies itself with other books in this
tradition. So if you are lured to it by the prospect of finding something
extraordinarily startling, but have first familiarised yourself sufficiently
with this type of literature, then you probably won’t find here anything
shocking. However, to its great
credit, and unlike other books of its class, this one covers a lot of ground
(virtually every school of notoriety of radical relativism) in a few concise,
enjoyable to read pages.
Yet, how many
more books of this kind are necessary? If you favour, like the authors do, say,
clear-thinking and intellectual honesty as our surer-footed approach towards
truth, then as many as it would take to keep denouncing those thinkers who
masquerade sound truth with wilful quibbling. More basically, WTM
sets out to raise and answer a number of foundational truth-related questions,
among them: Why should we even care about it? What are the best means at our
disposal to preserve it? How are we to distinguish complex and difficult
arguments from mere gibberish?
It seems
somewhat unfortunate that, in the apparent epistemic superiority of the 21st
century’s intellectual heights, this sort of message still needs to be stated,
and then restated. Some years ago, for
example, the Sokal Fallacy (Sokal
A., 1996) and The Postmodern
Text Generator (http://www.elsewhere.org/pomo)
seemed to do more than their share in exposing to the world the excesses of
sophistry of the extreme relativist community. But, as damaging as this academic
embarrassment seem to be to them, it proved insufficient to quell their writing
output. In hindsight, it might have just for awhile waned it. Consequently, the
authors argue that ‘new’, though fundamentally similar works will still keep
cropping up out of this original penchant for verbosity and deliberate
shadow-throwing.
Nonetheless, it should be marked at the outset that the
authors would not, in principle, oppose the efforts of those who labour
conscientiously and honestly (for this
attitude cannot be overstressed) in literary criticism and other
humanities-related fields — in the same spirit in which perhaps they might
disagree with the paradigmatically obtuse scientist who regards all art as
‘unreal’. But they’d
certainly insist that such efforts be carried out – in either case – with
responsible awareness regarding the epistemic reach and boundaries of their
respective disciplines and academic specializations. What Benson and Stangroom
seem to reject the most, then, are the arbitrary and uninformed incursions that
certain intellectuals make on fields in which they clearly show no competence,
as well as their indiscriminate tangle of the methods of art and literature with
those of science.
For instance, it
is worth noting that this was akin to the motivation that prompted physicist
Jean Bricmont’s (1996) exposé of
gender studies professors who, like Luce Irigaray, argue that ‘constructs’
such as Einstein’s equation can be ‘sexed’:
Sandra
Harding consistently refers to epistemology as ‘conventional’ epistemology
in contrast to standpoint or feminist epistemology, thus framing standpoint
epistemology as unconventional rather than potentially simply wrong. There is a
strange idea lurking behind this framing: that epistemology is a matter of
choice, and thus of fashion and convention, and of politics and commitment, as
opposed to being a matter of truth of falsehood, warrant or the lack of it. (Stangroom
& Benson, 2006: 46)
I have quoted this passage at some length not only
because it is representative of the book’s manifesto, but also because it
highlights, indirectly, a perennial philosophical dilemma. By definition, to be
sure, epistemology and philosophy are essentially-contested fields (Campbell
R.J., 2001); but the task of evaluating the merits of a given work, which
aspires to make some kind of contribution to them, has been also a conventional
and necessary feature shared by both.
The chief reason for this, I believe, is to prevent the virtues of scepticism,
one of philosophy’s cherished tools, from being mishandled by disingenuous and
sensational minds. Only in this manner can scepticism be rescued from
degenerating into the vices of fallacy that are pervasive in various forms of
“philosophy”. And, as Campbell (2001:341) states, “Bad philosophy, if it is bad enough, is not philosophy at all”.
Though its
arguments are simple, straightforward and unpretentious, the book is still
remarkably effective in retaining the interest of specialists. Although perhaps
is even more successful for its care in not showing, at the same time,
condescension towards lay readers. In so doing, it teaches by example: avoiding
the sometimes pedantic, discursive and muddled jargon of the trends of thought
it seeks to deflate. While it
is true in a few passages that the tone can be construed to swing from critical
to deridingly scathing, the authors try to make sure the change is duly
justified. And they do not need greater excuse than to merely reprint the
somewhat cynical titles of various articles and conference papers of the
academics they criticise. For Benson and Stangroom don’t have to fabricate any
straw man, since this type of research seems to be parodying itself. This is
specially the case in their discussion of “Institutions, Academe and Truth”
(chapter 7), when they talk about (p. 152) “the popularity of, shall we say,
surprising titles that accompanied the Theory explosion”:
Session
and paper titles which have graced the annual MLA [Modern Language Association]
convention include: ‘Jane Austen and the Masturbating Girl’; ‘The Muse of
Masturbation’; ‘Clitoral Imagery and Masturbation in Emily Dickinson’;
‘Desublimating the Male Sublime: Autoerotics, Anal Erotics, and Corporal
Violence in Melville and William Burroughs’… it is hard to read this sort of
thing without laughing…(p. 152)
This book is
thus peppered with similar examples, such as those of the third chapter, “The
Truth Radicals”, where WTM cleverly
groups together postmodernism and new age relativism — although this is
perhaps better achieved in the one that follows it, “The Social Construction
of Truth”. Here can be found excellent vignettes of those who contend that
‘truth’ is absolutely subservient
to the general ‘social’ ends of the particular cultural context within which
it was ‘constructed’. One can barely help recall Richard Dawkins’ (2003:
18) trenchant dictum: “If
you are flying to an international congress of anthropologists or literary
critics, the reason you will probably get there… is that a lot of Western
scientifically trained engineers have got their sums right.”
Dawkins, by the
way, gets his share of attention in chapter 5 of WTM,
“Politics, Ideology and Evolutionary Biology”, albeit in vindication and
defence of his views. The focus there is on the theoretically inane criticisms
of Dawkins’ detractors who, having little or no inking about issues in
contemporary genetics and ethology, endeavour persistently in trying to
discredit scientific claims. Further,
not content to limit their ‘criticisms’ to biology, they cast aspersions as
to the alleged political implications of Dawkins’ scientific ideas — going
as far as equating them, along with those of fellow biologist E.O. Wilson, with
social Darwinism and baron-robber capitalism. Needless to mention, these attacks
appear to be still more frivolous given the extensive and highly documented
repudiation that both scientists have made in relation to this matter;
considering, especially, that some of their arguments were voiced even before
these objections surfaced!
Finally, in
their closing chapter, Ophelia and Stangroom finish–quite predictably–with a plea to condemn the spurious rhetoric of
extreme relativists, whichever field they happen to be in. More importantly, by
conflating societal values such as ‘human flourishing’ and ‘happiness’
with clear, rational and methodical enquiry, their summons to the cause of truth
invokes a strong humanist component. And
thus, as they stress in the book’s last line: “That’s why truth
matters”.
REFERENCES
Bricmont, Jean (1996); “Postmodernism and its Problems with Science”, in Archimedes: A Journal for Science Teachers; Finland; LaTeX file.
Campbell,
R.J. (2001); “The Covert Metaphysics of the Clash between ‘Analytic’ and
‘Continental’ Philosophy” British Journal for the History of Philosophy;
9(2) 2001: 341–359
Dawkins, Richard (2003); A Devil's Chaplain: Selected Essays; Weidenfeld & Nicolson: London
Sokal, A. (1996); "A Physicist Experiments with Cultural Studies." Lingua Franca 62-64.