Consciousness, Literature and the Arts
Archive
Volume 4 Number 2, July 2003
_______________________________________________________________
Catalano, Joseph S. Thinking
Matter. New York, Routledge, 2000. 224 pages including bibliographical
references and indexes. ISBN 0-415-92665-3
Reviewed by
From
the title to the appendixes, Professor Catalano’s book is intelligent and
controversial. It sustains arguments that break with some commonplaces in the
philosophy of the last fifty years. Beginning the introduction, the author
points out his realist and materialist perspective, and his anthropocentrism. In
these positions he is arguing that nothing exists but the matter and that the
link between the mind and the world is our fleshy body.
Catalano
is opposing to reduce qualities to quantities. His anti–reductionism is very
important along this ambitious book. The author support a non–reductionist
materialism and criticises the operation that most of contemporary materialists
do when they try to reduce qualities into quantities and, at the time, pretend
to reduce the consciousness of qualities into quantitative relations. Catalano
observe that this pretension is not coherent: “while scientific
materialists deny the objective existence of qualities, such as sound, they are
realists to the extent that they claim that causes for our hearing sound exist
in the world” (p. 2). Catalano is continuing with the tradition initiated
by Hegel, and passing by Husserl and Bergson leads to Sartre; he assumed that
consciousness is a privileged experience that cannot be reduced into
quantitative relations.
Traditionally,
this non–reduccionist position could derive into a kind of idealism, and into
a dualism, as the one of Plato or Descartes, that conceived a world of qualities
and ideas separated from the quantitative material world. Catalano avoid this
risk when he affirms that consciousness and the perception of qualities take
place in the fleshy body. The entire body appears as a “collective organ of
thought” (p. 4), position clearly influenced by Jean Paul Sartre
and that resembles the affirmation that existential decisions involve not only
the subject, instead, the decision involve all the human kind.
Catalano’s
anthropocentrism means that we perceive the world as it is because our relation
with our body, that is used to make that we use to interact with the world in a
differentiated manner. Our consciousness, that sees the world with fleshy eyes,
reveal objects as visible and coloured, making a non–tetic consciousness of
the world and of itself. The non-tetic attribute signifies that we look at the
world without posing our human intentions into an amorphous matter, definition
borrowed from Sartre.
Consciousness
and qualities has quantitative aspects, that can be related in scientific
theories and the instruments we can use, that permit us consider qualities and
consciousness quantitatively. But Catalano wrote that there is no reason to
privilege scientific thought as if it were better than common thought and its
ways to perceive the world. Here Catalano criticize a common place in
contemporary philosophy that privileges scientific knowledge and takes common
thought as non-reliable. Catalano is taken this position from Sartre,
interpreting that the existentialist is hinting that “things are the way
they are because consciousness if fleshy” (p. 107).
The
continuous insistence in commonsense knowledge that gives us the world in its
relation to a fleshy organism let Catalano to criticize the preferences that
most of the contemporary philosophers give to scientific representation of the
world. There is a difference between water considered as the fresh liquid that
is capable to quench our thirst and the chemical formula of water as H2O.
Both are true, but belong to different worlds. The mechanical conception of body
privileges chemical conception, but for the common sense the conception of the
water defined by its qualities is better. The argument that is more true (if
this expression is permitted) the scientific conception of water leads to other
radical position, ¿why not take the mathematical relations as the very truth of
things? Then Catalano states that “... common sense, science, and art give
equally valid ways of interpreting our environment” (p. 83). This is very
near to the conception of Nelson Goodman.
The
emphasis in the anthropocentric view let Catalano make some interpretations of
Sartre’s philosophy, defining absurdity, a medullar concept in the French
philosopher: “... absurdity means that, without a relation to human
existence, continuity over time would not exist” (p. 70). Catalano propose
to understand the relation of common sense to history and to science, keeping
present that language is rooted in our organic fleshy body. We should research
different human activities and conceptions, “... returning to that of
common sense, that we are able to keep our fleshy feet on mother Earth”
(p. 94).
In
last chapters, language is considered as the totality of corporal movements and
its history, not as a formal system. From this point of view, language is the
basis of worldmaking.
The
book is divided into two parts, the first dedicated to explain the relation
between the thought and the world, the second, shorter than the first, explains
the link between names and things. The first part of the book contains four
chapters and the second has three, total: seven.
In
Chapter I, “Matter and Pure Enquiry”, argument that if “things exist
independently of our conceptions and linguistic expressions about them, but not
independently of their relations to the fact of our organic conscious existence.
This bond is a worldmaking, wrote Catalano borrowing Goodman’s conception of
worldmaking.
Catalano
is contradicting the brain–body dualism because he sees that is replacing the
Cartesian mind–body dualism. Instead, he emphasizes the reality of the entire
fleshy body. As consciousness takes the form of sight, things are made visible;
this is the reason why the body is a collective organ of thought. Catalano does
not deny the subjectivity, instead, he take it for granted. As he deny the
reduction of qualities to quantities, Catalano denied the possible reduction of
consciousness to quantities: “if red can exist in the world as a quality
irreducible to quantity, then consciousness is itself a quality irreducible to
quantity” (p. 19).
For
Catalano, Descartes eliminated fleshy body from thought and eliminated the
historical construction of languages, mathematics and numbers. Descartes begun
his reflection accepting a world of meanings that seem non-temporal and
a–priori and this is the condition for his dualism, grounded in his
ahistorical outlook on knowledge (p. 20).
A
polemic section titled “Molding the Knower to the Known” is developed to
criticize philosophers like Plato, Aristotle and Descartes that assumed that an
absolute conception of reality is possible and, then, they are independent of
any human existence. “They mold both the knower and reality in a way that
makes pure knowledge possible”. This peculiar way to criticize these
philosophers is rich and interesting.
In
this chapter is remarkable the emphasis in the historical process to acquire
knowledge. Descartes’s dualism is a “result of his mistaken belief about
inquiry as an ahistorical phenomenon”, stated Catalano. Descartes passed
through all the efforts from different scientist and philosophers and the result
is that he is amazed by the power of his own mind.
Chapter
2 continues Catalano’s efforts to ground his realism related to our organic
body. Is prominent the consideration that everything that appears as a fact is
an interpretation; knowledge is a worldmaking. Catalano’s most cogent
arguments against reductionism and opposite to the claim that science gives us
the essence of things are in this chapter.
The
Third Chapter explains Catalano’s ontological worldmaking, while Chapter Four
analyzes modal qualities from the anthropocentrically point of view that can be
synthesized in three points: 1. The fleshy unit of our body makes it meaningful;
2. Our body is t he source of language as a collective and historically forged
web of meanings; and 3. Our body is a source of possibilities. Catalano
recognizes that these points are taken from Sartre’s Being and Nothingness.
We have to recognize that Catalano is using these concepts in a more polemical
and a more didactic context than Sartre.
Chapter
Five explains how necessary and contingent qualities are both essential to the
definition of a thing, analyzing Kripke’s positions and Sartre’s. Chapter
Sixth is written in order to explain the distinctive features of Catalano’s
relational realism: qualities and natures perceived in a commonsense way truly
exist as essential features of the world; and the bond between qualities and
things is our fleshy body. The point is that we collectively mold matter into a
web of meanings and, gradually, we interiorize this web of meanings not
completely, producing the unconscious, a very illuminating direction to
understand myths.
In
the seventh chapter, Catalano explains universals as a particular aspect of the
collective making of artifacts, a set of meaningful relations that we
interiorize and give our personal stamp. Language is also a history of our
collective actions an artifact forged along an historical process. Is important
and very useful for the one who teaches children their first lectures, the
conception of reading as a comprehension of meanings, instead the conception of
a written language as a movement from sign to sign. Books are conceived as the
first form of artificial intelligence, because in the activity of writing books
the intelligence achieves more permanence and a degree of complexity not
available to conversation (p. 162).
Summarizing
the objections and postures of this intelligent book, Catalano rejects
scientific materialism because it masks “an unjustifiable transcendent
perspective of the world”. He objects pragmatism because it gives the
impression of certain skepticism about essences; “essences can be modest
earthy things [...] essences are not absolute...” They are always
in relation to something: our flesh, an equation or the structures of
experiments. (p. 170). His relational realism is also present in his insistence
in no neutral, no privileged and no absolute perspective from which to judge to
connect common sense, art and science.
The
book concludes in stating that “we connect everything with ourselves”.