Consciousness, Literature and the Arts
Archive
Volume 3 Number 3, December 2002
_______________________________________________________________
Necessary Fictions: Memoir and Self-Making
by
Gettysburg
College
Frances Mayes begins the memoir of her painful childhood as follows:
“At the frontispiece of childhood, a white goat pulls a painted cart.
A long-haired goat brushed to shine, with a garland of violets around its
ears. True red cart with wooden
wheels. I am standing up in it
wearing a sundress: a little Charioteer of Delphi . . .”(Mayes 1997, 131).
Though memoir can support a writer’s fantasies about what could have
been, or what should have been, in the end, memoir is bound to the truth of what
did happen. Mayes’ imagines what the frontispiece of the book of her
childhood ought to have looked like,
but when she gets down to telling her story, she tells us the uncomfortable
details of what she actually lived through.
“I wanted to be a child. . . I knew from stories and friends the
concept of childhood. Magic and
fairies and castles and the family going on family trips in the car over the
river and through the woods. Picnics
at the beach and family reunions and holding hands around the dinner table for
silent prayers. I wanted to be a
read-to child with a bedtime and warm milk and snow days . . .” (132). The
wish to have been the “read-to child” is crushed under the weight of her
memories: “[v]iolent nights: nothing to do except face each other. Southern
Comfort, recriminations, and if-onlys. Therefore,
childhood, that time I knew I was entitled to, was impossible” (132).
Memoir
deals with truth, unlike fiction that deals with fables, or philosophy that
entertains possibilities. Yet, how
meaningful is it to talk about “truth” in connection with the memories of
one’s life? How much are we
truthfully remembering what has taken place in our lives, and how much are we
reconstructing, remaking, and reordering the events of our lives in relation to
our hopes for the future? What I
will ultimately argue is that memoir, like philosophy, provides us with
necessary fictions, something akin to Immanuel Kant’s transcendental ideas,
rather than the mere fictions of art. These
necessary fictions, which are neither arbitrary nor merely fictitious, provide
us with the structures we desperately need to make sense of our lives.
Following
Aristotle’s dichotomy, and therefore hierarchy, in the Poetics, memoir stands in a closer relation to history than to
philosophy or poetry. Poetry is
more philosophical than history, claims Aristotle, since “its statements are
of the nature of universals, whereas those of history are singulars”
(Aristotle 1451b 7-8).
Universal statements are embodied in Characters, who represent
“distinctive qualities” such as goodness.
Characters represent what humans could be, or ought to be, rather than
what they all too often are. In
telling the story of her life, its singular events lived by a unique and
concrete person, Mayes’s work fails to reach the level of the Aristotelian
poetic or philosophical, since it is mired in the actual. Furthermore, because memoir, on this reading, is too bogged
down by in world of the particular, then we ought to conclude, if we are
following Aristotle’s Poetics, that
memoir cannot be a cathartic experience for the reader. The reader of memoir, it would seem, cannot find herself in
another’s story, because the memoirist does not “simplify and reduce [the
story] to a universal form” (1455a 8-9).
Or does she? Because it does
not portray the universal element in the unique tragedies of concrete persons,
on first glance it would seem that memoir does not serve for its audience as a
means for personal catharsis. Therefore, we must ask why it is that memoir has
such popular appeal? Why are we
drawn to the personal stories of others, others whose lives may seem in no way
like our own lives? Perhaps we
might need to expand Aristotle’s list of media that deal with the universal.
Memoir is the means by which memory seeks its origin.
Here origin is understood as arche,
or the principle around which one orients one’s life, or from which one acts
towards her proper end. Perhaps, as
in the case of Mayes, the memoirist writes in order to discover the origin of
the trauma that defines her life: her parents tumultuous marriage, the
drunkenness and the fighting which drew most of their energy away from their
daughter. Mayes’ writes to
discover an arche from which she might
also discover her future. “I said
many things to myself by the age of seven.
If I ever get out of here, I will
never select unhappiness” (138). While
it is true that the events of Mayes’ life might be too idiosyncratic to
represent a “universal form” of human action, the process by which Mayes’
labors to order her life through memoir is itself, I am arguing, a universal
form, what I will later call a necessary fiction. The desire to seek one’s
origins, to gather up the shards of memory into a unified whole, is therefore a
universal human desire. The desire
for origins, for wholeness, is likewise a desire to understand oneself in time.
Genevieve Lloyd writes “[t]his unifying of the fragments of experience
is epitomized in memory . . . and acted out in autobiographical narration”
(Lloyd 1993, 20). Time is the
schemata through which we collect the seemingly disconnected events of our
lives. Memoir, or autobiography, is
the form that unifies the fragments of one’s life after periods of trauma.
Kathryn Rhett explains, in the introduction to her Survival
Stories that, “[p]art of the task of the memoirist is to present the
‘I’—the persistent, changeful self—as wholly and forcefully as possible.
For the writer, constructing the ‘I’ is part of restoring life to
wholeness . . . Constructing the ‘I’ is part of surviving . . .” (Rhett
1997, 10). Hence, what we the readers find in memoir is a mechanism for ordering
one’s life.
Before
turning to Mayes’s memoir in order to seek clues for how one finds a structure
or form with which to order a life, I want to dwell a moment on whether my
inquiry is indeed an appropriate philosophical inquiry.
After all, for many philosophers, metaphysical questions concerning the
essence of one’s life are meaningless
questions[1].
Ever since Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason, philosophers have been engaged in dispute
over the proper boundaries of philosophy. Kant,
himself, ended the “Transcendental Analytic” with a discussion of the proper
terrain of philosophy in his famous metaphor of a island amid foggy banks,
threatening ice bergs, and rough waters:
We
have now not merely explored the territory of pure understanding, and carefully
surveyed every part of it, but have also measured its extent, and assigned to
everything in it its rightful place. This domain is an island, enclosed by nature itself with
unalterable limits. It is the land
of truth—enchanting name!—surrounded by a wide and stormy ocean, the native
home of illusion, where many a fog bank and many a swiftly melting iceberg give
the deceptive appearance of familiar shores, deluding the adventurous seafarer
ever anew with empty hopes, and engaging him in enterprises which he can never
abandon and yet is unable to carry to completion (Kant 1965, 257).
If
we remain safely on Kant’s island of truth, then we must restrict ourselves to
what lies within the limits of the island: the phenomenal world or the world
that can be experienced through our senses.
Yet, as Kant points out in this passage, we adventurous seafarers will be
lured off the island into dangerous and unknown terrain, moreover we will be
lured into terrain upon which we will not find stable footing.
This alluring world is the noumenal realm, in which reside purely
intellectual ideas, or in other words, what resides in the noumenal realm cannot
be experienced through the senses. Kant
writes, “We therefore demand that a bare concept be made sensible, that is,
that an object corresponding to it be presented in intuition.
Otherwise the concept would, as we say, be without sense, that is, without meaning” (260). What lures us away from the well-traveled terrain of the
island of truth are ideas which are meaningless because they cannot be intuited
by the senses. Ideas such as ‘that which orders my life’ are without any
sensory content. What we do well,
claims Kant, is organize sense data into objects of experience which can then be
studied through rigorous scientific investigation[2].
What we cannot help but do,
however, is search after the answers to questions about things that do not
reside on the safe island of truth. We
desire and hope for knowledge above and beyond what is given in experience.
Though we are confronted with the actual events of our lives, events
rooted in the spatio-temporal reality of Kant’s phenomenal world, we
nonetheless are forced to ask meta-questions about these events, questions such
as: “what do these events mean?, what do they suggest about my future?, what I
can hope for?” “…[T]he
concepts of reason,” claims Kant “aim at the completeness, i.e., the
collective unity, of all possible experience, and thereby go beyond every
experience. Thus they become transcendent” (Kant 1977, 70).
That is, though he insists that we need to be critical of reason’s
answers to these meta-questions, Kant nonetheless emphasizes that it is the very
nature of human reason to seek them out.
When Kant turns to the “Transcendental Dialectic,” he explains that
one of the functions of the transcendent ideas is to bring unity to the
subject’s understanding of herself—to fill in all those details not yet
experienced or perhaps not capable of being experienced.
Kant writes “they [the transcendent ideas] have an excellent and indeed
indispensably necessary, regulative employment, namely, that of directing the
understanding towards a certain goal upon which the routes marked out by all its
rules converge, as upon their point of intersection.
This point is indeed a mere idea, a focus
imaginarius . . . [which] serves to give to these concepts the greatest
[possible] unity . . .” (Kant 1965, 533).
What serves as the focus
imaginarius of a life is memoir. Nancy
Mairs writes “the only way I can find out is through language, learning line
by line as the words compose me” (Mairs 1993, 1).
In
the writing of one’s life, one strives to give shape, organization, and form
to one’s life. The writer, as St.
Augustine explains in his Confessions
“gather[s] together ideas which the memory contains in a dispersed and
disordered way, and by concentrating our attention we arrange them in order as
if ready to hand, stored in the very memory where previously they lay hidden,
scattered and neglected” (Augustine 1991, 189, X, v.18).
In memoir, the mind focuses the fragments of one’s life through the
locus of memoir: the form. However,
the form, the shape one gives to one’s life is not, in the Kantian framework,
something that we can discern from the experience of our life.
What makes our life hang together is not something which we take in
through the senses, rather it is a purely intellectual idea, a focal point which
reason gives to the mind so as to regulate, or to order one’s life.
These
intellectual ideas, however, in no way refer to anything in the world that we
can empirically verify. Transcendent
ideas, like the pure intuitions of space and time, and the concepts of the
understanding, for Kant, are a priori
principles. A priori principles do
not correspond to real things in the world, nor are these principles “mere
fictions.” Summarizing his
deduction of the pure intuitions in his Prolegomena,
Kant explains “But in regard to the latter [space] the principle holds good
that our sense representation is not a representation of things in themselves,
but of the way in which they appear to us.
Hence it follows that the propositions of geometry are not determinations
of a mere creation of our poetic imagination, which could therefore not be
referred with assurance to actual objects; but rather they are necessarily valid
of space . . .” (Kant 1977, 31). The apriority gives us the necessity
of the determination, and the validity comes from the fact that all subjects
determine the world through these same principles.
A priori judgments are subjective universals.
Hence, one ought not conclude, in the case of space, for example, that
“the space of the geometer would be considered a mere fiction.”
Rather, “this formal intuition, is the essential property of our
sensibility by means of which alone objects are given to us, and if this
sensibility represents not things in the themselves but their appearances, then
we shall easily comprehend, and at the same time indisputably prove, that all
external objects of our world of sense must necessarily coincide in the most
rigorous way with the propositions of geometry” (31). The apriori principles of the sensibility and the
understanding provide us with the universal, subjective foundations for knowing
the world as it appears to us—the well-traveled terrain of the island of
truth—whereas the apriori principle of reason provides us with the universal,
subjective foundations for making judgments in the non-empirical world—the
rough waters surrounding the island of truth.
Kant cautions us not to confuse the concepts of reason, or the
transcendent ideas, with the concepts of the understanding because the judgments
made by the understanding refer to objects, while the judgments made by reason
refer to the subject. That is, we
can never take ourselves as an object for empirical investigation.
But
what is common to all of these judgment is this: they are all of them necessary
fictions. The apriority gives these
judgments necessity—all subjects will be led to make these same judgments
either about the world, or ourselves. Yet
because these judgments do not correspond in anyway to things in themselves,
they are, strictly speaking, fictions. These are not “mere fictions,” that is creations of our
“poetic imagination,” but the necessary structures through which all human
beings must think themselves and the world.
We have no immediate intuition of either the world, or intellectual ideas
such as what unifies the self. We
must always mediate our comprehension of the world and ourselves through these
transcendental structures, which are not “representation of things in
themselves,” but nonetheless the necessary structures with which we must all
use in perceiving, understanding, and judging.
Now
that we have clarified what is meant by “necessary fictions,” let us return
to Mayes’ memoir in order to grasp what seems to be the universal form, or
judgment about her life, that she uses to organize the events of her life.
Reflecting on how much her own life fell short of the what a normal
child’s life ought to be, Mayes makes a promise to herself “If I ever have a
child, I’d say to myself, I’ll give her a normal life” (133).
If her own parents were too narcissistic to give her what any child
deserves, then Mayes will take control of the situation and give to her daughter
what any child deserves: a normal childhood.
Now, one could conclude that the transcendent idea, or necessary fiction,
which brings into focus Mayes’ life is the idea that children ought to have
childhood with “[m]agic and fairies and castles and the family going on family
going on family trips in the car over the river and through the woods.
Picnics at the beach and family reunions an holding hands around the
dinner table for silent prayers . . .” (132), so that she will make certain
that this will be the life of her daughter.
However, as one reads on, it becomes clear that the fantasies of what a
childhood ought to have been—the rosy picture of the child charioteer and her
goat which should lie on the cover of her book like a fairy tale— are mere
fictions. Mayes’ best friend, the
one who appeared to her to live this charmed childhood: “their house had
French doors that opened onto a long porch with a swing, beds with dips in the
middle like nests. Happy mother and daddy who called her by a nickname leftover
from baby talk. I could not be there enough.
There was no chink. Ribbon
candy always filled the same dish on the sideboard.
We licked peach ice cream off the wooden beater . . .” tells her years
later how “her mother in the kitchen had shot herself in the mouth with a
rifle. Gingerbread on the counter and her teeth stuck in the
ceiling” (135). Mayes’ fantasy
of how childhood ought to have been made her blind to the principle which
actually structures a life. Moreover,
her promise to give her daughter a normal childhood is broken—not because
Mayes lacks the strength of character to give her daughter such a life—but
rather because of tragedies which befall her daughter, tragedies that no one can
avoid: the death of her daughter’s friend and the death of her horse riding
instructor. Mayes confesses:
“I’m striking wet matches if I think I’m in charge of her childhood.
Fealty to the dark will be extracted” (137).
“Fealty to the dark,” is the necessary fiction by which Mayes orders
the events of her life. What is
most traumatic is the mere fictional belief that we are in control of our lives,
that we can actually be in charge of our children’s lives.
The belief that her parents deprived her of what was owed to her, a
normal childhood, is a mere fictional belief, a fantasy, which will ineluctably
lead her to fragmentation, to breakdowns, and to traumatic disappointments.
What will give her back wholeness is the recognition of this principle:
“fealty to the dark will be extracted.”
Either we acknowledge that all “things fall apart” and that is what
defines human lives, or we stubbornly hold onto the belief that what ought to be
a human life is a life free of darkness, free of suffering, free of trauma. But this latter belief will continually be challenged by the
fact that we do not have control over how our lives will unfold.
Whether we “court danger,” as Mayes claims her mother did, or with
white knuckles try to make life for ourselves and our loved one as charmed as
possible, “fealty to the dark will be extracted.”
The
presence of light will always be interrupted by the absence of darkness.
Hope will always be punctuated by moments of disappointment.
So the writer who tries to pull together these moments of absence with
other moments of presence, will find in the writing, in the structuring of the
memoir this principle: while we cannot control what will happen to us, we can
control what we think we were owed by the world and others.
Either we can foolishly hold onto a belief that life ought to be
“normal,” that is, free from trauma, or we can recognize that life is really
a series of events we have far too little control over save what we think we
were owed. Mayes’ childhood
housekeeper, Willie Bell, is the one who trys to teach her this simple truth:
“She offered me not sympathy, but a steady point of view.
One sass at the table and out I had to go to pick my switch in the yard.
As I stalked through the kitchen, Willie shook her head.
‘When are you going to learn,’ she said quietly, ‘just don’t talk
back’” (143).
Mayes’
memoir, entitled “Talking Back,” does not turn out to be an indictment of
her parents, nor an indictment of the world, for that matter, she is not talking
back in this sense. Instead, this
memoir allows her to recover moments of “grace”—it is more a taking back,
a reclaiming, than mere, sassy, back talk.
In a life held up to the fantasies of what life ought to be like, there
is a nothing but disappointment. Though
no human being, especially the memoirist, can know with objective certainty what
a life ought to be like, Mayes shows us the necessary fiction, the transcendent
idea, by which we must all live our lives, namely “consequences are random”
(143).
Works
Cited
St.
Augustine. 1991.
Confessions.
Translated by Henry Chadwick. Oxford:
Oxford University
Press.
Kant,
Immanuel. 1965.
Critique of Pure Reason.
Translated by Norman Kemp Smith.
New York: St. Martin’s
Press.
----------------.
1977. Prolegomena
to Any Future Metaphysics. Translated
by Paul Carus.
Revised by James W. Ellington. Bloomington:
Hackett Publishers.
Lloyd,
Genevieve. 1993. Being
in Time: Selves and Narrators in Philosophy and
Literature. London:
Routledge.
Mairs,
Nancy. 1993.
Ordinary Time: Cycles in Marriage,
Faith and Renewal. Boston:
Beacon Press.
Mayes,
Frances. 1997.
“Talking Back,” in Survival Stories: Memoirs of Crisis. Edited
by Kathryn Rhett. New York:
Anchor Books.
Rhett,
Kathryn. 1997.
“Introduction,” in Survival Stories: Memoirs of Crisis. Edited by
Kathryn Rhett. New York:
Anchor Books.
[1] “Pure reason require us to seek for every predicate of a thing its own subject, and for this subject, which is itself necessarily nothing but a predicate, its subject, and so on indefinitely (or as far as we can reach). But hence it follows that we must not hold anything at which we can never arrive to be an ultimate subject, and that substance itself never can be thought by our understanding, however deep we may penetrate, even if all nature were unveiled to us. For the specific nature of our understanding consists in thinking everything discursively, i.e., by concepts, and so by mere predicates, to which, therefore the absolute subject must always be wanting . . .” (Kant 1977, 75).
[2] “All pure cognitions of the understanding have the feature that the concepts can be given in experience, and the principles can be confirmed by it; whereas the transcendent cognitions of reason cannot either, as ideas, be given in experience or, as propositions, ever be confirmed or refuted by it . . .” (Kant 1977, 71).