Consciousness, Literature and the Arts
Archive
Volume 6 Number 2, August 2005
Special Issue: Literary Universals
_______________________________________________________________
Somatic Marking, Ethical Sense, and Practical Reason: The Political Economy of Literary Universals from Richardson and Austen to Dostoyevsky and Grass
by
Auburn University
Recent work on literary universals (e.g., that of Patrick Colm Hogan) suggests that there is a deep, cross-cultural concern with the place of empathy and bodily feeling—what Antonio Damasio calls “somatic marking”—as a counterforce to in-group identification. However, the precise delineation of this universal concern changes historically and culturally. One significant parameter affecting such variation is political economy. In the following pages, I consider what difference the rise of capitalism makes to the cultivation of somatic marking in relation to in-group identification. Specifically, the first section takes up, synthesizes, and extends work by Damasio, Hogan, and others on empathy, and work by Giddens and others on modern political economy. The purpose of this section is to establish a general account of the phenomena that is sensitive to both universal and variable features. The second section considers exemplary works from the early period of capitalism, taking up novels by Richardson and Austen. The final section moves to the period of “mature” industrial capitalism and “late” capitalism, examining works by Dostoyevsky and Grass.
Empathy and Political Economy
Consistent with much research exploring the neurological and developmental interrelatedness of cognitive and emotional faculties, Damasio has presented clinical findings suggesting that humans cannot process mental images of violence or suffering without being physiologically disturbed in ways measurable through monitoring the autonomic nervous system (2003: 147-55; 1999: 40-49; 1994: 174-206); such mental images are “somatically marked.” Damasio found exceptions only in two sets of subjects—those suffering from patterns of brain damage that deaden emotions and debilitate practical reasoning, and those previously diagnosed as sociopaths. Patients in whom such emotions “as embarrassment, sympathy, and guilt” appeared “diminished or absent” had histories of poor decision-making (2003: 144-45). Joseph LeDoux notes that “Damasio and colleagues interpreted their results in terms of an inability of patients with orbital cortex damage to use emotional information to guide action, and have proposed that emotional information or knowledge normally biases reasoning ability by influencing attention and working memory processes,” but suggests that since “the orbital cortex is part of working memory circuitry, and is especially involved in working memory about emotional information,” Damasio’s results may “show a dissociation between cognitive and emotional aspects of working memory” (2002: 253).
Separately
or in combination, the work of Damasio and many others reveals how “crucial
internal coordination between brain systems is in maintaining the unity of mind
and behavior” (LeDoux 2002: 306), implying species-wide biological bases for
literary depictions of how absence of empathy yields not only morally abhorrent
behavior, but also self-impoverishing, self-defeating judgments. Although this
theme is a literary universal recurring in historically and geographically
diverse literatures worldwide (cf. Hogan 2003b: 17-30), the advent of capitalist
societies and the modern nation-state alters significantly how the issue is
framed. Rather than presenting the dissociation of practical judgment from
affective life as a “missing the mark” (hamartia),
a constitutive vulnerability of the human condition and a “flaw” to which
the most successful among warrior elites were particularly prone, nineteenth and
twentieth-century fiction becomes increasingly concerned with how the
ideological and material conditions of modernity invite, coerce, or naturalize
the stripping away of somatic marking from mental images. Concurrently, that
fiction becomes increasingly diffident about literature’s ability to repair
the psychic and social damage inflicted by culturally induced distortions of
emotion’s proper role in guiding attention and shaping memory.
Damasio
observes that the "effect of a 'sick culture' on a normal adult system of
reasoning seems to be less dramatic than the effect of a local area of brain
damage,” but then adds, “there are counter-examples," such as Nazi
Germany and Stalinist Russia, and he notes, "I fear that sizable sectors of
Western society are gradually becoming other tragic counter-examples"
(1994: 178-79). In pre-modern cultural contexts, and thus in literature
reflective of those contexts, the threat of forfeiting practical rationality
through losing affective receptivity to the suffering of others is tied to the
exigencies of political economies in which wealth-creation and material, social
well-being are inseparable from successful exercises of direct violence.1
Such states, as both classical Western history and precolonial African or Indian
history attest, were nearly always at war, with war both consolidating and
decomposing the state.2 People were thus exposed to direct violence
(from raiding, conquest, subjugation, internal lawlessness--as in private
armies, piracy, banditry). Significant differences in the felt texture of daily
life and in habitual relations among people follow from political economies
structured around the coercion of the lash as opposed to the coercion of
increasing or decreasing wages.
To
distinguish, as Anthony Giddens does, between “direct” and
"indirect" violence or coercion does not imply that the latter is
characterized by an absence of violence or coercion, nor does it suggest that
capitalism's extension or operation need be devoid of recourse to
"direct" methods: the British opium wars and de facto child slavery in
sweatshops illustrate that capitalism may indeed underwrite direct violence.
Nonetheless, it is analytically useful to distinguish between daily exposure to
death, abduction, robbery and daily exposure to administrative or social
pressures.
A
society’s patterns of accumulation and authority may delimit and distort
receptivity to somatic marking, either by encouraging us to discount emotional
influence in guiding attention or by encouraging us to segregate emotional and
cognitive working memory. However, the way stories engage and hold interest,
binding together affective and cognitive aspects of mental life through
reinforcing and playing upon involuntary, empathetic identification with the
imagined experience of others, seems to work against such segregation. In The
Mind and Its Stories (2003), Hogan argues that similarities in plot and
theme from historically, geographically disparate cultures reflect universal
patterns of prototypical narratives that “are, in their broad structure,
expansions of the micronarratives that define our emotion terms” (88). When
characters are depicted in certain circumstances, we imagine the emotions those
circumstances would elicit from us, drawing upon working memory of what
experiencing the given emotion “feels like,” and then associate that
“feeling” with a mental image of the character. Consequently, “the
proximity of a literary narrative to prototype cases of eliciting conditions”
for emotions in our own lives “facilitate[s] the immediate, unself-conscious
lexical identification of the emotion, which is a crucial part of empathic
identification” (89).
Empathetic
identification with elicited emotion, however, may also reinforce appropriative
and ethnocentric forms of identity. In his survey of worldwide narrative
patterns, Hogan argues, drawing on the work of Keith Oatley and Philip
Johnson-Laird, that “emotion is the product of an agent’s evaluations of
his/her success or failure in achieving particular goals within what is, in
effect, a narrative structure” (76). The goals an agent pursues relate to
happiness—that is, our own personal flourishing and that of groups or ideas
with which we identify. Hogan observes, “romantic
union and social or political power are the goals sought by protagonists in
prototypical narratives” (94, Hogan’s italics). While the romantic union
prototype associates happiness with personal flourishing or fulfilled desire,
the social or political power prototype encourages empathetic identification
with “in-group domination” and would seem to naturalize an “entire society
aspir[ing] to (deserved or rightful) domination over other societies” (111).
The second prototypical narrative would thus seem to facilitate delimitations of
somatic marking encouraged by political economies predicated upon direct
violence.
Both
forms of happiness may be seen as reflecting the origins of emotional-cognitive
interconnectivity. Damasio identifies the “narrative structure” of pursuing
happiness with Spinoza’s notion of conatus,
“the relentless endeavor . . . of each being to preserve itself” (2003: 36),
or the quest of organisms for “what we as thinking and affluent creatures
identify as wellness and well-being”
(35). The remarkable number of culturally central narratives that render
problematic triumphant in-group domination, however, suggests that the very
blunting of affective responsiveness to others—especially to ethnic, class,
and gender others—that facilitates military and social domination undermines
the kind of practical reasoning that sustains individual and group conatus. Hogan notes the worldwide pattern of “the epilogue of
suffering,” in which narratives built on plots of power do not end with the
protagonist’s victory but go on to describe the “pain following the achievement of social dominance” (123) [Hogan’s
emphasis]. Arguing that when we attend to narratives, “[e]thical enjoyment is
a sort of second-order enjoyment,” predicated upon “ongoing ethical
evaluation of actions guided by other sorts of goals [romantic union, power]”
(132), Hogan suggests that “epilogues of suffering” negotiate tensions
between two kinds of ethical prototypes drawn upon for evaluating narrated
action—“the prototype of group defense” and “the prototype of
compassion” (136-37).
To
the extent that the registering of somatically marked images upon consciousness
precludes affective indifference toward what is processed cognitively, both
images of another’s suffering and a story’s calling our attention to them
may be experienced as disruptive challenges to the habits of cognition
underlying an ethics of group protection, and so a potential threat to conatus
(hence the hostility Euripides, for example, provoked in his fellow Athenians).
The absence of such susceptibility, however, may constitute no less a threat,
for hardening the self against destabilizing affective appeals invites ethical
insensibility and political obtuseness. Unchecked egotism and rage in The
Illiad nearly undo the Greeks. Cultural acknowledgement of the value to
individual and group conatus of even
abrasive literary challenges to in-group moral and political complacency
underlies the preservation of such tragedies as The
Trojan Women, however ambivalently contemporaries may have viewed Euripides.3
When pre-modern narratives acknowledge that the socio-political order seems to demand, even reward, affective insensibility, they often acquire the tonalities of tragedy, portraying what seems an intractable double-bind: pursuing and securing power is inherently damaging to affective life, but a damaged affective life is inherently unstable, joyless, and materially-politically destabilizing. Such a basis for tragedy remains in place as late as Racine’s Phèdre (1677), especially in the portrait of Theseus, but there tragedy is presented as adhering to a material, political, ideological past disjunctive with the world inhabited by Racine’s audience, a world whose twin pillars are the nation-state and mercantile capitalism.
The great political appeal of capitalism, as both the rhetoric of Adam Smith’s The Wealth of Nations (1776) and the analysis of Giddens make plain, rests upon its promise to dissociate wealth-accumulation from direct exercises of violence and so make expanding commercial networks the means of securing stability within and peace among nations. The natural efficiency Smith ascribes to capitalistic wealth-creation had a sharply ethical dimension. It was to distance everyday life from habitual fear of, and coarsening by, violence, and it was to “refine” manners so that they would cease to reflect “archaic” systems of violent accumulation and authority. Significantly, Smith wrote The Theory of Moral Sentiments (1759) before turning to economics, and belonged to the Scottish Enlightenment, whose accounts of history defined progress as the reordering of ambitions and passions away from tragically repeated cycles of “in-group domination” yielding not happiness but the fruits to “darkened” practical reasoning—exploitation, tyranny, fanaticism, and thus fractious, ruinous civil disorder.4 Whig rewritings of the West’s, and especially Britain’s, story into narratives of progressive refinement of morals, expansion of liberty, and flourishing of commerce are, of course, highly problematic. Nonetheless, the ideal or possibility of dissociating empathetic identification with “in-group domination” from complicity with “in-group” violence and subjugation shifts the focus of anxieties about culturally induced damage to affective and reasoning faculties from the structural conditions of power and prosperity to the seductive appeal of forms of conceptual rigidity and somatic atrophy that normalize indirect violence. By describing pre-modern history—Western and non-Western—as vicious cycles of blunted affectivity and defective practical reasoning, writers as diverse as Voltaire, Montesquieu, Hume, and Robertson advocated the legitimacy—indeed, the ethical imperative—of overthrowing forms of thought that initiated or recuperated such cycles.
Empathy, Early Capitalism, and the Novel from Richardson to Austen
The novel, as pioneered by Richardson, creates protagonists who, unlike Achilles or Theseus, seek forms of empowerment ideally conducive to progressive excisions of vestiges of direct violence from material and social life. The primary obstacles confronting them highlight the dangers posed by ideologically articulated conceptual rigidity and somatic atrophy. As Anna Howe tells Clarissa, a woman’s defense of sociable, civilizing power in private, domestic life becomes inescapably a public concern: “Every eye, in short, is upon you with the expectation of an example” (Letter 1, 40). If the world transformed by capitalistic accumulation and the nation-state’s administrative structure cannot provide a credible space for bourgeois feminine narrative agency, then its pretensions to separate authority from triumphant arbitrary violence and material well-being from coercive appropriation risk being exposed as frauds.
Although
the notion that the novel was created in England in the 1740s has rightly been
modified to acknowledge that Richardson’s and Fielding’s relations to their
(largely female) predecessors were both complex and vexed,5
it is important to recognize that their narratives did in fact
strike contemporaries (female no less than male) as something fundamentally new.
Sarah Fielding notes in 1749 that “the Author may thank himself for”
Clarissa’s being “treated like an intimate Acquaintance by all her
Readers,” whereas “the Authors of Cassandra,
Clelia, with numberless others I could
name, were never in any Danger of having their Heroines thought on, or treated
like human Creatures” (14-15). Similarly,
Diderot in 1761 argued that Richardson’s “personnages ont toute la réalité
possible” (31) and claims, “J’ai entendu disputer sur la conduite de ses
personnages, comme sur des événements réels; louer, blâmer Paméla, Clarisse,
Grandisson, comme des personnages vivants qu’on aurait connus, et auxquels on
aurait pris le plus grand intérêt” (37). Sarah Fielding, imagining a series
of dialogues on Clarissa, constructs
fictional versions of just such kinds of discussions.
Richardson
and Fielding create fictions that represent in private, domestic life patterns
quite similar to those delineated by Whig historiography’s accounts of public
life: stunted affective responsiveness and defective practical reasoning do in
the world of novels what provincial dogmatisms and irrational consistencies do
in national histories. Indeed, Fielding correlates Squire Western’s Jacobite
sympathies with his propensity for domestic patriarchal tyranny. Both writers
suggest that specific ideas—associated with socio-historically specific
political, religious, ethnic self-understandings and interests—encourage
self-enclosed, asocial conceptual rigidities. Their novels imply that if such
notions become embedded in core dispositions, they will work to block
“natural” moral imperatives, communicated somatically and involuntarily,
from shaping judgment and guiding conduct. The quintessential example is
Lovelace’s repeated recourse to the slogan, “Once subdued, always
subdued,” to argue himself out of the feelings Clarissa’s presence and
discourse elicit (430-31). In Letter 187: 1-4, the editor describes Lovelace as
being “upon the point of making a violent attempt” when “he was checked .
. . by the awe he was struck with” in “seeing as he thought her spotless
heart in every line” of her “terrified but lovely face” (602). Lovelace
seeks to evade by interpretative revision the ethical claims enunciated by his
own flesh’s somatic responsiveness to the image of her suffering. He recasts
his own sensations in terms of mock personification and apostrophe: “Oh
virtue, virtue! . . . what is there in thee that can thus affect the heart of
such a man as me, against my will!--Whence these involuntary tremors, and fear
of giving mortal offence?” (602). Forced to acknowledge that he has been
“exceedingly affected,” finding himself
“ashamed to be surprised by her into such a fit of unmanly weakness,”
he immediately resolves “to subdue it at the instant, and guard against the
like for the future.”
On
the one hand, as the first generation of novel readers frequently stressed, the
new fiction solicited an unprecedented intimate and sustained affective
immersion in the sensations, sentiments, and experiences of fictional
characters.6 On the other hand, critical approbation of
Richardson’s and Fielding’s works depended upon viewing them as distinct
from the novels of amatory intrigue of Behn, Manley, and Haywood, which were
widely perceived as encouraging uncritical empathetic identifications with
unprincipled characters’ pleasures and worldly successes.7 Readers
who approved of Richardson and/or Fielding did so by affirming that entering
vicariously into what another’s life must feel
like yields a visceral ethical concern that anchors rather than suspends
critical judgment. Diderot argues that because the reader, despite himself,
participates in Richardson’s work (“on se mêle à la conversation, on
approuve, on blâme, on s’irrite, on s’indigne”), “Richardson sème dans
les coeurs des germes de vertus qui y restent d’abord oisifs et tranquilles,”
virtue being understood as “un sacrifice de soi-même,” so that “on se
sent porter au bien avec une impétuosité qu’on ne se connaissait pas. On éprouve,
à l’aspect de l’injustice, une révolte qu’on ne saurait s’expliquer à
soi-même” (30-31).
Diderot’s account of reading the new fiction also describes much of its content. The obtuseness of Clarissa’s parents’ and uncles’ letters, the self-satisfied smugness of Rev. Brand’s discourses, as well as the weak, cowardly, trite locutions of a host of minor characters underscore with encyclopedic relentlessness all the ways that people misapply and hide behind culturally sanctioned notions to evade being unsettled by somatically impressed ethical sense.8 Despite pronounced formal and thematic differences, both Richardson’s and Fielding’s novels insist that somatic responsiveness to images of another’s suffering awakens rational deliberation and calls us to our best selves by binding together emotional and cognitive aspects of working memory. Thus in Tom Jones, when Tom would urge Nightingale to divest himself of conventional ideas of “honor” in relation to Nancy Miller, he invites him to contemplate a succession of mental images modeled upon Hogarth prints: “[S]ee this poor, unhappy, tender, believing Girl . . . . Paint to your Imagination the Circumstances of her fond, despairing Parent . . .” (768).
Novelistic depictions of how somatically registered ethical sense progressively refines practical rationality become increasingly subtle once Jane Austen develops, through indirect free style, a technique evoking felt experiences of intercommunication and mutual modification between what Damasio terms “core consciousness” and “extended consciousness” (cf. 1999: 168-233).9 Core consciousness occurs whenever “the brain forms an imaged, nonverbal, second-order account of how the organism is causally affected by the processing of an object” (1999: 192). By contrast, extended consciousness involves memories, projects, habitual dispositions, all of which together generate what Damasio calls “an autobiographical self,” so that the “imaged, nonverbal, second-order accounts” of core consciousness are put in dialogue with a particular temporally-extended sense of, and practice of, being an autobiographical self: “Extended consciousness occurs when working memory holds in place, simultaneously, both a particular object and the autobiographical self, in other words when both a particular object and the objects in one’s autobiography simultaneously generate core consciousness” (1999: 222, Damasio’s emphasis).
Damasio argues that in humans “the second-order nonverbal narrative of consciousness can be converted into language immediately,” but consciousness precedes language, not only because “babies and animals” have consciousness, but also because “the very nature of language argues against it having a primary role in consciousness. Words and sentences denote entities, actions, events, and relationships. Words and sentences translate concepts and concepts consist of the nonlanguage idea of what things, actions, events, and relationships are” (1999: 185). Such an account of language’s structure as non-arbitrary and non-self-referential, as grounded upon embodied experience of material realities, is consistent with developmental psychological studies of how pre-verbal infants generate emotional and cognitive concepts from abstracting prototypical schemas or memory structures from repeated experiences (Bucci 1997: 138-51). While not denying either the structural modeling of language upon nonverbal embodied experience or the evolutionary priority of nonverbal working memory, LeDoux stresses the transformative effect of language upon human working memory, noting that “the human prefrontal cortex has . . . access to a processing module specialized for language use,” and that language “radically alters the brain’s ability to compare, contrast, discriminate, and associate on-line, in real time, and to use such information to guide thinking and problem-solving. The difference between having only nonverbal working memory and having both verbal and nonverbal working memory is enormous for how the cognitive system works” (2002: 197). LeDoux highlights how what Damasio describes as “conversion” or “translation” of nonverbal narrative into language transforms cognitive capacities, yielding “a revolution rather than an evolution of function” (198).
Jane Austen finds ways to represent in words the dialogues between core and extended consciousness, nonverbal and verbal working memory, that bind the pulsations of immediate sensory awareness to a continuous, individuated, reformative, and principled sense of self. By dramatizing the interplay between a character’s core and extended consciousness, Austen puts in play the reader’s own relation between core and extended consciousness. The experience of mentally processing an Austen novel is necessarily one of participating in the protagonists’ refinement of, or reparation of, bonds between somatic responsiveness and practical rationality—in Austen’s language, bonds between feeling and reason, sensibility and sense. For example, in Chapter 6 of Pride and Prejudice (1813), Austen interrupts the reader's congealing identification with Elizabeth to describe briefly Darcy's evolving reflections. While Darcy had "at first" looked at Elizabeth "without admiration," and "when they next met, he looked at her only to criticise," he begins to find her face "was rendered uncommonly intelligent by the beautiful expression of her dark eyes. To this discovery succeeded some others equally mortifying. . . . [H]e was forced to acknowledge her figure to be light and pleasing; and in spite of his asserting that her manners were not those of the fashionable world, he was caught by their easy playfulness. Of this she was perfectly unaware;--to her he was only the man who made himself agreeable no where, and who had not thought her handsome enough to dance with" (15).
Austen's
abrupt shift in point-of-view forces upon us an evaluation that pulls us away
from empathetic identification with Elizabeth’s perceptions and thus disturbs
our participation in her appraisal of her “success” in measuring the worth
of others, and so our sharing in the pleasurable emotions Elizabeth’s
appraisal generates. We learn that, as she suspects, Darcy did indeed originally
grasp her as an object of cognition and rendered her an item consistent with his
assumptions, habits, and self-importance; she was inscribed into a haughty,
self-satisfied, “imperialistic” extended consciousness, one shaped by the
indirect violence of class and gender privilege. He regards her as a type, and
one he is “in no humor at present to give consequence to” (7), for, like
Lovelace, he has internalized expectations that those outside his circle cannot
“touch” or modify him, much less “give” him
something of “consequence.”
However,
in the passage above we see that Darcy's narrative self-consciousness can
be interrupted precisely because core consciousness—registering bodily
affective vulnerability, including erotic receptivity—may "speak
back" to conceptuality, and so complicate and refine judgment. Involuntary,
embodied cognitions address us, as it were, behind the back of ideology,
undercutting our efforts to simplify our inner life by delimiting affective
responsiveness to those of our own group. "Forced to acknowledge" that
her figure was "light and pleasing," "caught" by her
manners' "easy playfulness," Darcy encounters "discoveries"
that are "mortifying." Austen links the language of sense with the
sense of language. Somatically articulated interruptions of on-going narrative
self-consciousness initiate an ethical calling of the self to account, but
interruption alone, as Lovelace’s case dramatically illustrates, cannot
sustain such a process. Darcy is described as seeking the language that will do
justice to his own sensations, which "surprise" his intentionality by
challenging his quick, automatic assimilation of Elizabeth to a category of
outsiders (poorly bred young ladies aspiring to advantageous marriages)
threatening to his conatus and that of
the groups and ideas with which he identifies. Darcy has reasons to be on guard,
for, as Austen shows through the example of Charlotte Lucas, many young ladies
were susceptible to considerable indirect coercion to “market” themselves
advantageously. But through experiencing "surprise," Darcy knows that
he has been unjust in some respects (and thus possibly in others), and his sense
of the justice owed Elizabeth is inseparable from his quest for the proper
words, words that might do better justice to sensory, non-verbal, "felt
immediacy." While Darcy’s pride is certainly implicated in his experience
of “mortification,” of recognizing a mistake in judgment, what gives that
cognitive mistake ethical significance for Darcy is the conscious, continuous
moral self-evaluation integral to his extended consciousness. Indeed, Austen
almost always reserves the term “mortifying” and its variants for morally
sensible characters. Wickham and Mr. Collins, Mrs. Elton in Emma
(1816) and the Crawfords in Mansfield Park
(1814), may occasionally make discoveries, but rarely “mortifying” ones.
Wickham and Lydia’s behavior upon their return to Longbourne after their
scandalous marriage is representative: their “easy assurance”
“disgusted” Elizabeth and “even . . . shocked” Jane; Elizabeth
had not believed Wickham “equal to such assurance,” but resolved “to draw
no limits in future to the impudence of an impudent man. She
blushed, and Jane blushed; but the cheeks of the two who caused their confusion,
suffered no variation of colour” (216).
While
the body's openness to affect means that our words are about something other
than themselves, their degree of adequacy is an ethical as well an
epistemological issue only if the extended consciousness processing the images
delivered by core consciousness experiences itself as obliged to do justice.
Darcy is emotionally affected, feels “mortification,” because he “is
forced” to evaluate negatively in the case of Elizabeth his success in
pursuing a particular goal—justice to others.
Much
Austen and novel criticism of the past twenty years, under the sway of various
theoretical reductions of moral life to effects of power or desire, seeks to
interpret the impress of ethical sense upon characters and readers as strategic
hegemonic manipulation.10 Such a sense of obligation must indeed be
cultivated intentionally and inculcated culturally if it is to adhere to verbal
working memory (in Austen’s language, if it is to act as a “principle”).
Both Austen’s depictions of ethical subjectivity and contemporary cognitive
science research, however, offer good reasons to believe that such a sense of
obligation, however verbally codified in consciousness as “principle,” is
not imposed by arbitrary cultural conventions upon subjectivity (as an
effect of hegemonic ideology or a “duping” by morality), but rather is
rooted in pre-intentional, transcultural, bodily registerings of ethical
significance. Austen describes characters who habitually integrate such
registerings into extended consciousness as “sensible,” and those who will
or cannot as “insensible.” Her insistence that genuine human well-being (conatus) depends upon affective receptivity to ethical significance
modifying practical reason may therefore be seen as a prescient anticipation of
contemporary research into the role that registering ethical significance plays
in biologically normative human cognitive and affective life. Reciprocally, this
role may reflect the evolutionary anteriority of ethics to human development (Damasio
2003: 160-75), and so support, on scientific, materialist grounds, the
humanistic contention, at the heart of Austen’s work, that an insufficiently
developed ethical sense deprives one of a life of full human flourishing. When
Elizabeth hears of Charlotte Lucas’s mercenary acceptance of Mr. Collins,
“to the pang of a friend disgracing herself and sunk in her esteem, was added
the distressing conviction that it was impossible for that friend to be
tolerably happy in the lot she had chosen” (88). Elizabeth’s judgment is
confirmed not just by the portrait of Charlotte’s married life in Kent, but
also by her perception, upon parting with Charlotte, that “though evidently
regretting that her visitors were to go, she did not seem to ask for compassion.
Her home and her housekeeping, her parish and her poultry, and all their
dependent concerns, had not yet lost their charms” (149). In that “not yet
lost” is inscribed a chilling future.
The
clinical evidence Damasio presents that we are biological programmed to be
somatically responsive to mental images of human suffering and Harold Scheub’s
demonstrations of how African oral storytellers communicate significance by
"eliciting and ordering emotion-evocative images” (14-15) suggests that
narratives address their readers' freedom by soliciting affective responsiveness
to verbal images crafted to simulate immediate, "sensible" visual and
other sensory images. We accept as proper Darcy’s mortification over finding
he has not done another justice because Austen’s depiction recalls to working
memory our own similar sensations (cf. Hogan 2003b: 45-75; 2003a: 140-65). We
must, of course, actually have such
emotional schemas available to working memory (cf. Bucci 1997: 127-37) and must
be adept at processing how language elicits them. Not everyone can “get” it:
Mrs. Bennet, Mr. Collins, Miss Bingley, Lady Catherine would no more understand
Darcy’s mortification than they do his humor. Nor is it simply a matter of
intelligence or even a kindly nature, as the portrait of Mary Crawford in Mansfield
Park particularly attests. However, what this lack of universality
illustrates is not the arbitrary nature of compunction or humor, but rather that
if we have no access to, or are induced to block access to, all that works to
revise previous judgments and to make our self-images and conceptualities
answerable to justice, then we are unable to distance ourselves from the side of
our conatus that “automatically” registers those “unlike
ourselves” as potentially threatening outsiders (Damasio 2003: 163; LeDoux
2002: 220-21). We become estranged from full human well-being to the extent that
we become unable to register our own cognitive violence to the Other. This is
most forcefully illustrated in the letter Mary Crawford writes Fanny speculating
“playfully” on how the death of the gravely ill Tom Bertram would enhance
the appeal of his younger brother Edmund: “Fanny, Fanny, I see you smile, and
look cunning, but upon my honour, I never bribed a physician in my life. Poor
young man! –If he is to die, there will be two poor young men less in the
world; and with a fearless face and bold voice would I say to any one, that
wealth and consequence could fall into no hands more deserving of them” (423).
That Mary cannot gauge the rhetorical effect of such discourse upon Fanny and
Edmund suggests not that their restraint reflects stuffiness or hypocrisy, but
that Mary’s habituated inability to hear accents of cognitive violence in her
own words and thoughts disempowers her, betrays her to an impolitic, imprudent
volubility that follows naturally from, and so documents with merciless clarity,
an extended consciousness that is morally tone-deaf.
Once
registered, however, awareness of our own participation in cognitive violence
cannot but be felt as "mortifying”—if
we resemble Darcy rather than Mary, if we have not, through miseducation or
emotion-blunting circumstances, lost the capacity for ethical evaluations of the
narratives of our own lives. Mr. Collins, Mrs. Bennett, Miss Bingley, Lady
Catherine, Lydia, and Wickham are of course paradigms of such culturally induced
or accommodated “brain damage.” The indirect violence structuring the
English gentry world Austen portrays, in which those financially or socially
marginalized can normally hope to gain a degree of power or security only
through cultivating patrons or gaining husbands with fortunes, subtly but
insistently coerces a veiling of motives from oneself as well as others and a
disinclination to allow any somatic registering of ethical significance to
disconcert extended consciousness. Mr. Collins’ groveling flattery, for
instance, is uninhibited by a sense of shame that would be, for the purposes of
insinuating himself into the good graces of Lady Catherine, dysfunctional. Such
social coercion, however, is ethical violence.
Lydia
likewise illustrates how the mechanisms of indirect coercion in the emerging
capitalist nation-state depend upon and naturalize self-indulgent and
self-regarding forms of value—money, social status, fashion (as in Lydia’s
mania for new hats)—that work against conceiving one’s goals, one’s
“narrative structure,” in ethical terms. As the portrait of Lydia’s
“wild volatility” and “disdain of all restraint” (159) attests, unless
one is so educated as to integrate ethical consideration into intentional
subjectivity, and thus inscribe the sense of “principles” into verbal
working memory, whatever original embodied, involuntary capacity one may have
had for somatically registering ethical sense will atrophy; one will become
“beyond the reach of amendment” (159). In Mary Crawford, Austen presents a
more intelligent and kindly, but older and so calcified version of Lydia. Edmund
breaks with Mary once he hears her condemn her brother Henry’s seduction of
Edmund’s married sister as merely “folly” and joke that, had Fanny
accepted him, Henry would have been “too busy” to think of the sister
(441-42). Edmund notes that Mary’s making light of the matter denotes not
“cruelty” but rather “total ignorance, unsuspiciousness of there being
such feelings,” a “perversion of mind which made it natural to treat the
subject as she did,” faults not “of temper” but of “principle, . . . of
blunted delicacy and a corrupted, vitiated mind” (442)
By
suggesting that a “natural” ethical subjectivity must be acculturated, and
that Lydia’s “wild” lack of compunction, Collins’ weakheadedness, Lady
Catherine’s arrogance, and Wickham’s egotism are natural and yet products of
culturally induced “brain damage,” Austen is not guilty of incoherence, but
anticipates the principle of “plasticity” in cognitive science, which has
displaced nature/nurture dualism with notions of what LeDoux calls “nurturing
nature”: “Most systems of the brain are plastic, that is, modifiable by
experience, which means that the synapses involved are changed by experience,”
while “Plasticity in all the brain’s systems is an innately determined
characteristic” (2002: 5, 8-9). Synaptic pathways that are not activated are
not conserved, and the more synaptic pathways are employed the stronger their
connections will become; one must, LeDoux notes, “use it or lose it”
(75-96). “Genes, environment, selection, instruction, learning—these all
contribute to the building of the brain and the shaping of the developing self
by wiring synapses” (96). In portraying the insensible “natures” of her
less admirably characters, Austen shows us the chilling consequences of a
cultural violence that, by encouraging identification with debased values,
normalizes benign neglect as a parenting style, and naturalizes a screening off
of extended consciousness from disturbing impressions registered upon core
consciousness, thereby debilitating practical reason.
For
Darcy, Elizabeth, Emma Woodhouse, and other positive characters, however,
affective, somatic interruption by core consciousness initiates a process of
cognitive, ethical reconfiguration of extended consciousness motivated by the
desire not to be inconsistent to the "ideal" self he would construct
through habitual practice. In the passage from Chapter 6 (15), well-being (conatus)
is defined in a way that shifts the group whose dominance one identifies with
happiness from an ethnic or class order to a community of the sensible and
rational—which thrives on differences of temperament and background (as the
novel’s concluding image of the society of Darcy, Elizabeth, and the Gardiners
indicates). Thus, the ability to be “touched” by another’s word or look is
central to the capacity to perceive one’s own cognitive violence, as the
description of Emma’s reflections upon Mr. Knightley’s reproach of her joke
at Miss Bates’ expense attest: “Never had she felt so agitated, so
mortified, grieved, at any circumstance in her life. She was must forcibly
struck. The truth of his representation there was no denying. She felt it in her
heart. How could she have been so brutal, so cruel, to Miss Bates! How could she
have exposed herself to such ill opinion in any one she valued! And how suffer
him to leave her without saying one word of gratitude, of concurrence, of common
kindness!” (299). As the prominence of the romantic union prototype in
Austen’s fiction suggests, such a shift of group identification from ethnic or
class communities to the community of those one rationally values is not only
consistent with “moral” concern for benefiting one’s own genes, but also
exposes the violence and self-impoverishment of what Austen describes as our
lapses in “prejudice,” which we may perhaps see as an evolutionarily derived
predisposition to suspect outsiders.
Notably, at the point in Pride and Prejudice when Austen allows us to glimpse Darcy’s mortification, Elizabeth, as yet uninterrupted by an equivalent somatic responsiveness, is borne along by the conventional consistencies of Merryton social judgments. Elizabeth's thinking at this juncture not only echoes her mother's; it lapses into the kind of impersonal generality Heidegger associates with "das Man." By concluding the paragraph with such a barbed portrait of her heroine, Austen seeks to stimulate in her reader an interruption akin to Darcy's, not only by breaking in upon Elizabeth as the "center-of-consciousness," but also by breaking in upon the genre conventions, gender identifications, and market expectations of courtship novels—ultimately rooted in empathetic identifications with the happiness of protagonists seeking romantic unions and power.11 But, as Austen is quite aware, such interruptions often need frequent reiteration before their "mortifying discoveries" can be acknowledged. If students' responses are any guide, most people, upon first reading the novel, notice this paragraph's interruption as little as they notice the narrative's intimations that Darcy and Wickham are not as Elizabeth construes them. Austen works self-consciously against the naturalization of complacency that identifications with novelistic heroines induce in less demanding fiction. Her narrative invites the extended consciousnesses of her readers to “enjoy” Elizabeth’s and Emma’s delight in their own powers of discernment in order to make the narrative's interruptions of that enjoyment inaugurate an imaginative, hermeneutical labor analogous to, and preparatory for, the ethical labor of allowing somatically registered disruptions of complacency to chasten and reform practical rationality. The happiness such a process opens is ideally figured in Elizabeth and Darcy's conversation, courtship, and marriage.
Despite all the forms of naturalized indirect violence Austen portrays as adhering to English gentry life, she suggests that the best aspects of that society—a certain cultural attentiveness to consideration, a sense of gratitude to others and of obligation implicit in privilege, a cultivation of wit and delight in good humor—make possible sufficient affective responsiveness that personal and communal moral growth are, if not normative, at least imaginable. By inspiring admiration and imitation of her heroines and heroes, by effecting the integration of affective and cognitive working memory in the course of reading, Austen’s fictions seek to render what is imaginable increasingly possible.
Literature and the Fate of Somatic Marking in Mature and Late Capitalism
In contrast to the cultural optimism that ultimately underlies Austen’s social criticism, Dostoyevsky in Crime and Punishment (1866) anticipates much twentieth-century and contemporary fiction by suggesting that Western modernity makes normative the stripping away of somatic marking from mental images so as produce the kind of “sick” cultures that Damasio fears “sizable sectors of Western society are gradually becoming” (1994: 179). However, Dostoyevsky does not share later writers’ crisis of confidence about either the irreparability of cultural damage to affective and rational life, or their doubts about literature’s efficacy in redressing the harm done. Through Raskolnikov, Dostoyevsky suggests that "understanding" (ponimanie) derives from "immediate" (neposredstvenoy) ethical, natural "sensation" (oshushchenie), which is able to "touch" us (oshupivat) in ways that disrupt ideological self-enclosure, opening extended consciousness to intermittent but insistent reformative interruptions that only the most obdurately willful egoism can ignore.
After
visiting the pawnbroker to "rehearse" his murder, Raskolnikov is
"decidedly confused" (reshitelnom
smushchenee) by an upsurge of disgust: "Oh God! How loathsome [otvratitelno] all this is! . . . No, it's nonsensical, it's absurd!
. . . Yes, that's what is it is: filthy, mean, vile, vile! [gryazeno,
pakostno, gadko, gadko!]" (39-40/9). Martha Nussbaum notes that disgust
"has a close relationship to shame's concerns about bodily
insufficiency," that it "expresses a refusal to ingest and thus to be
contaminated by a potent reminder of one's own mortality and animality,"
and that "[a] ubiquitous reaction . . . is to project the disgust reaction
outward, so that it is not really oneself, but some other group of people, who
are seen as vile and viscous . . ." (2001: 201, 205). Through the word
“vile” (gadko), Raskolnikov
expresses visceral repugnance both toward his own half-playacting planning of
the murder and toward the pawnbroker’s predatory manner and milieu, implicitly
identifying his projected self with her actualized self. To the extent that
Raskolnikov would appropriate the pawnbroker’s wealth, he identifies happiness
with the prototypic plot structuring her grasping identity and actions, but such
identification, linking his conatus with hers, strikes his core consciousness over and over
again as appallingly vulgar and terrifyingly invasive. He fears losing his
boundaries, his integrity, being “swallowed up” by the very forces,
attitudes, and narrative structure that his imagined crime would protest against
and lift him above. His involuntary ethical intuition and bodily disgust,
directed at both the pawnbroker and himself, block agency: Raskolnikov can only
move "as if irresolute" ["kak
bj v nereshimoste" (4)]
Unable to imagine happiness apart from an increasing acquisition of power, Raskolnikov is drawn to murder in part to deny, in part to punish himself for being unable to deny, identification with the plot of power realized with coarse frankness by the pawnbroker: rather than “bleeding” people continually, he would shed blood once; rather than taking whatever one can get from anyone, he would take only what he needs from one person who is without redeeming social or moral qualities. But Raskolnikov’s very need to distinguish his pursuit of happiness from the pawnbroker’s suggests that he cannot help knowing that such claims are delusive. He seeks to persuade himself that his intended violence follows “logically” from a practical reason “unprejudiced” by conventional pieties, that it is anchored in a “higher” or more authentic moral sense, and so, like the “indirect” violence of capitalism or nation building, is defensible, even commendable. What inhibits an easy conscience, however, stands outside the ideological frameworks that abstract violence into a calculus of utility. As long as extended consciousness remains “in dialogue” with a core consciousness that involuntarily registers somatic marking, unexpected or unregulated feelings will inform an understanding of ethical significance too immediately merged with bodily sensation to allow uncomplicated identification with a “happiness” of personal or in-group dominance won at the expense of others, even one other. Raskolnikov’s abiding susceptibility to ethical embodied sensations and their retrieval of affective memories is most clearly manifest in his dreams of the old mare and then the landlady being beaten (89-95/35-38, 157-58/71). As Robert L. Belknap notes, the subconscious Dostoyevsky portrays, unlike Freud’s, “is deeply moral; Rasknolnikov’s dreams and impulsive actions struggle against his rational mind’s rejection of moral values” (2002: 136).
In
the absence of cultural discourse reinforcing intuitions of ethical
understanding, however, natural physiological defenses against dissociations of
emotional and cognitive working memory may be progressively undermined. Notably
the murder becomes a live possibility for Raskolnikov, as opposed to a
self-tormenting mental game, only after he receives his mother's letter
rationalizing his sister's self-sacrificing engagement to the egotistical
businessman Luzhin.12 There
Dostoyevsky presents conventional, self-sacrificing, nineteenth-century maternal
speech as both willfully self-deluded and suffocating in its total subservience
to a son who is "everything" ["u
nas vse"] and loved "infinitely" ["bespredelno"] (73/27). Raskolnikov's mother’s discourse
encourages him to avert his gaze from his sister’s compromising of herself for
his benefit by inviting him to share the “story” the two women have arranged
in their minds, that Dunya’s actions are defensible, even commendable, because
conducive to the long-term “happiness” of the family, and especially of
Raskolnikov. Such maternal discourse constitutes an apology for “indirect”
violence and a model for hardening oneself against the discomfort of somatic
marked images that would disrupt identification with the forms of
“happiness” in “dominance” that modern society grants the beneficiaries
of indirect mechanisms of accumulation and authority. The mother’s letter
reveals how normative indirect violence has become in “respectable” society,
and how indirection, permeating private as well as public life, does not
diminish the actuality of violence. Raskolnikov is disgusted, viscerally
repulsed, by simply picturing to himself what his mother and sister would make
of him. On the one hand, he does not want to be incorporated into maternal plans
consistent with a natural order governed by rapacious self-interest; on the
other, he is revolted by the injustice of taking his place in the sun at the
expense of others (78-79/29-30).
The
“advanced,” “scientific” theoretical discourses that shape
Rasknolikov’s intellectual life conspire with the ideology behind his
mother’s discourse to marginalize or “explain away” somatically mediated
ethical unease in the name of a nature without God, in which "justice"
and “love” have been displaced by the highly “indirect” mechanisms of
socio-cultural “progress” or “rationalization” allowed by Whig-Hegelian
historiography and capitalist-utilitarian theory. After coming to the aid of a
victimized girl, Raskolnikov, upon reflection, repudiates the unmediated ethical
feelings that led him to concern himself with her, because he finds such
feelings intellectually indefensible, and thus cognitively unaccountable:
"They say that each year a certain percentage has to go off down that road
. . . in order to give the others fresh hope and not get in their way"
(85/33). Dostoyevsky portrays a world in which what "they say" (govoryat)
and what mothers say dovetail sufficiently to induce estrangements of extended
consciousness from somatically impressed ethical sensations. As a result,
subjectivity is internally split (raskol)
and prone to depressive violence.13
Dostoyevsky's
novel constitutes an effort to reconnect conceptual, verbal symbolization to
pre-conceptual, nonverbal sensory experience, and so to undo the estrangement of
practical reason from somatic responsiveness that both public and private life,
both intellectual and domestic discourse, were, in his view, making increasingly
normative. Fashioning a narrative in which terms denoting "feeling,"
"sensible," "sensitivity," "sensual" (tieuvstviovat)
consistently indicate the body's abiding access both to a world outside
subjective, ideological constructions and to ethical intuitions anterior to
intentional consciousness, Dostoyevsky opens readers, through their empathetic
identification with Raskolnikov, to experiencing the re-integration of
receptivity to somatic marking and extended consciousness in ways that allow
transformative interconnections with others (preeminently figured in the
relationship with Sonya and the other Marmeladovs) to lead one ultimately to
spiritual and moral “rebirth.”14
For
most of Crime and Punishment, however,
the kind of dialogical interactions between somatic responsiveness and practical
reasoning that Austen depicts in Pride and
Prejudice remain blocked, not because Raskolnikov is "insensible” in
the ways that Mr. Collins or Luzhin are, but because repeated incursions of
somatically-mediated sense into Raskolnikov's extended consciousness do not
re-form Raskolnikov's sense of self, as opposed to disrupting and convulsing it,
until the end of the novel. Each time "life" seeks to come to
Raskolnikov's aid by so affecting him somatically that he will be "forced
to acknowledge" what is from the perspective of ideology, pride, and
self-love "mortifying," he takes the embodiment of ethical sense to be
a violation of his freedom. Even audacious, prideful Raskolnikov, however,
cannot ultimately resist a natural (and, in Dostoyevsky’s view, divinely
ordained) “healing” intercourse between somatic responsiveness and practical
reasoning. In the final paragraphs, when "In the place of dialectics life
had arrived" (630) ["Vmesto
dialektiki nastupija zeizei" (331)], the narrative describes
Raskolnikov with terms in which natural, organic "fruition" and
sustained, conscientious application ["virabotatsja"
(331)] combine to allow the employment of the adjective "gradual" to
Raskolnikov, as in "a man's gradual renewal, his gradual rebirth"
(630) ["postepennogo obnovjenija
cheloveka, . . . postepennogo pererozedenija ego" (331)]. But, as
Dostoyevsky emphasizes, that would be a "new" ["novogo"] story.
Nevertheless, the ending of Crime and Punishment affirms Dostoyevsky’s confidence in the resiliency of healthy human instincts and so the efficacy of novelistic art in undoing the psychic, cultural damage wrought by “sick” societies. Such confidence is notably absent from Grass’s The Tin Drum (1959), in which the willfully stunted, obdurately three-year-old Oskar, like nearly all the other characters, is so self-enclosed, so somatically wounded, that the subject of literature becomes the loss of the subject. In The Tin Drum, the characters who populate Oskar’s lower middle class Danzig milieu resemble him just as he resembles his grandfather, Joseph Koljaiczek, who seeks refuge from an external world defined by politically violent, morally bankrupt power relations by hiding under "the wide skirts" of Oskar's grandmother. Koljaczek becomes a political outlaw when he sets fire to a sawmill where he works after his boss, enraged that Koljaczek paints a fence white and red (the national colors of a Poland then partitioned between Germany and Russia), beats him with a slat from the fence (27/19). Pursued by the police for a number of subsequent politically motivated arsons, Koljaczek finds nowhere to hide in an open potato field except under Oskar’s grandmother’s wide skirts, which “favored the same potato color” (18/11-12).
Linking capitalism (the sawmill) to imperialistic nationalism (the Prussian seizure of eastern Poland and establishment of German political-economic hegemony), Grass highlights both the predication of indirect modalities of violence (the authority of the sawmill boss, the administrative-surveillance machinery of the police) upon direct violence (military conquest), and the ways that pre-modern forms of in-group dominance are at once masked and articulated by industrialized political economies (through the disciplinary mechanisms of wages, property rights, etc.). Danzig and its environs rebut Whig-Enlightenment claims that uncoupling wealth-creation from direct violence will reform communal practical rationality by uprooting archaic “tribal” loyalties and break down “traditional” delimitations of affective responsiveness to one’s own group. By reworking the political trope of the highly organized, but unimaginative and repressive Germans (the police) battling a Polish resistance (Koljaiczek) marked by disorganization, grand but ineffectual gestures, mercurial courage and foolishness, Grass establishes the contrast, central to postmodern fiction, between an all-enveloping, soulless and inexorable System that circumvents or co-opts or subjugates all that would stand outside its sway, and a resistance that can only be uncompromised as long as it is anarchic, episodic, destructive, and so a “counter-force” ironically parasitic upon the order it subverts and thus doomed to self-marginalization.15
In the absence of a socio-economic, cultural-political order that can entice and sustain the kinds of subject formation that Austen and Dostoyevsky portray, social relations can hinge upon nothing more than asocial infantile regression. Oskar, whose narrative inverts the Bildungsroman’s pattern of progressive development,16 comes into existence thematically as well as biologically because his grandfather, "unable to tear himself away from her skirts, followed [his] grandmother" ["folgte (s)einer Großmutter, klein und breit Joseph Koljaiczek, der nicht von den Röcken lassen konnte"] (25/17).
Oskar's magical attributes—his refusal to grow up, substitution of drumming for speech, glass-shattering voice—entail a blunting of somatic responsiveness born of revolt against a public and private world that is incapable of engendering a sense of gratitude or connection. As Jürgen Rothenberg notes, Oskar’s self-isolation is “vor allem Negativentscheid, Aktion gegen etwas: Am Anfang steht der Protest!” [“above all negative decision, action against something: In the beginning is the Protest!”] (1976: 10). Such negatively instigated identity, evocative at once of German Idealist philosophy, Koljaiczek’s anarchic-quixotic nationalism, and existentialist-postmodern accounts of freedom, is deeply problematized by Grass’s novel. Oskar's affective impoverishment grants him a detached clarity of vision, but only at the price of rendering him, at best, intermittently and inconsequentially capable of being "touched" and thus moved by either the somatic marking of images or the sociability implicit in speech. Oskar describes himself as "one of those clair-audient infants whose mental development is completed at birth [‘deren geistige Entwicklung schon bei der Geburt abgeschlossen ist’] and after that merely needs a certain amount of filling in” ["sich fortan nur noch bestätigen muß"]. The moment I was born I took a very critical attitude toward the first utterances to slip from my parents . . ." (47/35). Grass's German stresses the ethical implications: "geistige" denotes "spiritual," "humane," as well as "mental"; "abgeschlossen" "closed up," "self-contained," as well as "completed"; "bestätigen" "confirm, verify, endorse." In the next clause, curiously not translated, Oskar describes himself as "[s]o unbeeinflußbar . . . als Embryo," so inaccessible to influence as an embryo, that in the womb he listened to and regarded only himself (35). Viewing his parents as "small, bent over, gummed up" (47/35), Oskar rejects "[his] father's projects" for him, the expectation that he will inherit and manage the family grocery store (48/37).
Of course, Oskar’s account is notoriously unreliable: it is fantastic, there are internal inconsistencies, and he is writing from a mental hospital (see Reddick 1974: 82-86). However, to the extent that sardonic dismissal structures Oskar’s relation to the world, such judgment involves a lucid assessment of the “gummed up” characters among whom he lives. Oskar’s two putative fathers, the German Matzerath and the Pole Jan Bronski, reveal their limitations by reenacting national stereotypes: Matzerath is dull but reliable, Bronski idealistic but ineffectual; Oskar’s mother, wife of the one and mistress of the other, finds neither capable of assuaging her inner hunger. Similarly, the neighbors and fellow lodgers are, with rare exceptions, self-involved and contracted. As Patrick O’Neill points out, “Oskar’s distorted refraction of German society strips away the façade of respectability and reticence veiling the rise of Nazism in Germany”; rather than following from “some kind of almost supernatural eruption of evil incarnate,” it “was the coordinated channeling, on a huge scale, of the petty viciousness, the petty hypocrisies, the petty greed and frustration and spite and boredom of very ordinary people . . .” (1999; 24). Oskar's refusal to grow up follows from there being little in the adult world around him to inspire affection, much less imitation, but it also involves refusing, or seeing no point in, participating in a dialogue between somatic, affective responsiveness and practical reason that might make life in the world, and connection with others, appealing.
The much-noted scene in which Oskar, accompanied by his mother, Bronski, and Matzerath, sees a longshoreman fishing for eels using a horse’s head as bait underscores the disgust awakened by the spectacle of rapacious pursuit of well-being, conatus in its rawest form: the eels eat the horse’s head as humans eat eels, just as the gulls eat up the mother’s regurgitated breakfast (149-53/120-23).17 Matzerath’s affected indifference, though “green about the gills” [“der Käse in Gesicht”] (151/122), his cheerful eagerness to prepare eel delicacies, and his intellectualized complacency, “Don’t carry on so, pussycat. You’re always known how they catch eels and you’ve always eaten them just the same” [“Hab dich nich so, Mädchen. Hast doch gewußt, daß Aale da ran gehen und hast trotzdem immer, auch frische gegessen”] (153/123), recapitulates the pattern Raksolnikov follows in talking himself into indifference toward the distressed girl he encounters on the streets, as well as prepares us for Matzerath’s later easy acceptance of a Nazi ideology that extends to human beings the notion that creatures live naturally, and thus in a morally indifferent manner, from consuming one another. The “narrative structure” Matzerath embodies repels Oskar no less than the pawnbroker’s “narrative structure” repels Rasknolikov.
But the alternative to Matzerath’s affected, intellectualized “manliness,” Bronski’s apparent affective responsiveness, is no less marked by rapacious feeding upon another. When Oskar sees Bronski so solicitous of the mother’s distress that he looks “as if he were going to cry” [“als wenn er weinen wollte”] (151/122), his heart is “full of praise for Jan Bronski,” but he soon notices that Jan and his mother want to take advantage of Matzerath’s preoccupation with cooking eels for engaging in amorous caresses: “Jan stared at me; I knew I was in their way” [“ich . . . ließ mich von Jan fixieren und spürte genau, wie ich den beiden im Wege war” (155/124). Retreating into a clothes’ closet, Oskar watches as equivalent spectacles (which he calls “Act Two, Act Three”) Matzerath’s cooking and Jan’s pleasuring of his mother (157-58/126-27). Because Bronski’s sensibility resolves itself into narcissistic indulgence, and because the mother’s lovemaking revolves around self-pleasuring, both the “narrative structures” offered by romantic union and by power resolve themselves into crass forms of conatus that disgust Oskar and find their most thorough-going, horrific realization in the Nazi adventure.
Just as Oskar here retreats from an inter-personal world offering no patterns for empathetic identification, withdrawing into the narcissistic enclosure of the clothes’ cupboard, so, at the very dawn of his existence, only the prospect of acquiring a drum keeps him "from expressing more forcefully [his] desire to return to the womb" ["dem Wunsch nach Rückkehr . . ."] (49/37). The drive for well-being bifurcates between aggressive appropriation (of which fascism and sentimentality are both alternative and complementary aspects) and an autarkic withdrawal ultimately no less imperialistic.
The private symbolization of drumming, like his later erotic life, substitutes for Oskar's dominant desire—to retrieve prenatal self-enclosure, which entails abrogating any distance between himself and the object of desire—at once melting into her and incorporating her into himself. While his affective impoverishment—for the most part, people and objects engage his attention with identical levels of interest—secures him against being influenced by the dubious ideologies and fantasies that function as "wide skirts" for the adult characters, Grass insists that Oskar's anarchic activities not be understood as "resistance." Although he plays a fox trot to disrupt SA rallies, he also disrupts every other conceivable group (124/100), for his drum dismisses whatever others "might have to sing, trumpet, or proclaim" because they cannot compete with being beneath his grandmother's skirts (124-25/100-01). On the one hand, Oskar is unmoved by the social, political, cultural values circulating in pre-war Danzig because he is disgusted by the eel-eating greediness underlying every desire to be “filled up” with well-being; on the other hand, Oskar is unmoved because he believes that any “filling up” short of “wide skirts,” prenatal self-enclosure, will leave one hungry.
Oskar's self-isolating obsession, exemplified by his preoccupation, as
World War II erupts, with acquiring a new drum, the closest he can get to “Rückkehr,”
is mirrored in the tranquilizing obsessions of the other characters. Describing
the German assault on the Danzig’s Polish Post Office, Oskar observes,
"We were all happy . . . Jan Bronski had found all his skat cards including
the seven of spades, and Oskar had a new drum . . ." (235/191). Bronski's
skat playing, Matzerath 's delight in his SA uniform, the neighborhood
greengrocer Greff's frolicks with pretty boy scouts, and Oskar's drumbeating are
equivalent substitutes for "wide skirts," equivalent means of seeking
to be “filled up.” The prominence of smell in Oskar's erotic life
underscores its narcissistic, regressive structure; just as the odor of rancid
butter, like of the color of potatoes (the subsistence crop), is associated with
the grandmother's skirts, so "the first time [he] breathed in the effluvium
peculiar to Lina Greff," it "outshouted, engulfed, and killed all
vanilla," associated with Maria (304/250), the shopgirl who initiates Oskar
sexually and who Matzerath makes his second wife.
John
Reddick distinguishes between a “’brainbox’ Oskar” whose lack of affect
makes him a modern picaro, able to delineate with great cognitive skill the fraudulence
and delusions of a social world that does not “touch” him, and a
“’tears’ Oskar,” who is “emotionally involved” with, and thus
victimized by, the world he portrays (1974: 58-82). Reddick differentiates two
aspects of the “tears” persona; “if it is unfulfilled love that first
confounds him, it is a consuming sense of guilt
and fear that finally drives him to
despair” (77; also see Arker 1989: 179-90). Love objects “touch” Oskar
because they become, like his drums, substitutes and metaphors for a desire
coordinate with other rapacious forms of conatus—indeed,
Oskar’s campaigns for Maria, Lina Greff, and the circus-entertainer Roswitha
are repeatedly correlated with German military operations (266/217-18,
270-71/221-22, 305/250, 329/270). The touching of Oskar’s core consciousness
by guilt, however, like the disgust informing his rejection of the adult world,
suggests that recalcitrant, involuntary registering of ethical significance is
universally tied to human embodiment, for Oskar, even more than Raskolnikov,
strives to shield identity against destabilizing, reformative ethical sense.
Oskar
first demonstrates a capacity for guilt after his mother dies following
overeating and excessive lovemaking in the wake of the eel episode (implicitly,
she “stuffs herself” because neither what Mazerath nor Bronski offers is
consistent with genuine or sustainable well-being). Oskar asserts that he
“drummed her into her grave. Because of Oskar she didn’t want to live any
more; he killed her” (171/138). Immediately after this declaration, Oskar
confesses that he was “exaggerating” to impress Roswitha, and the circus
manager Bebra tells him that he wants to believe himself more important to his
mother than he was, which suggests how easily “guilt feelings” collude with
a sentimental narcissistic “feeding off of” others (see Reddick 78-79; Arker
237-60). Even so, the experience of guilt is irreducible to acting out. After
noting that he used his size to escape capture by the Germans seizing the Polish
Post Office while Bronski was sent to his death, Oskar describes himself as
‘filled with shame” (247/201), and observes, “But on days when an importunate
feeling of guilt, which nothing can dispel, sits on the very pillows of my
hospital bed, I tend, like everyone else, to make allowances for my ignorance”
[“Doch wie jedermann halte ich mir an
Tagen, da mich ein unhöfliches und durch nichts aus dem Zimmer zu weisendes
Schuldgefühl in die Kissen meines Anstaltsbettes drückt, meine Unwissenheit
zugute . . .”] (248/ 201-02). Although guilt can often feed vanity, and
though we seek to evade its pain, and so work against allowing
“mortification” to reform extended consciousness, “Schuldgefühl”
can be, as here, experienced as “unhöflich,”
external to economies of desire and power, as impressed somatically into our
processing of mental images—“in die
Kissen . . . drückt.”
The
possibility that such somatic responsiveness to ethical significance might—at
last—yield moral development is glimpsed only once. Oskar begins,
unexpectedly, miraculously, to grow physically after he renounces the
consolations of drumming out of guilt over having occasioned Matzerath’s death
at the moment of Nazi defeat (403-07/ 333-37). Oskar’s guilt-stricken
renunciation of the instrument sustaining his self-involvement is notably linked
to his repeating the phrase, “I should” (“Ich
soll”), binding identity to the verb denoting ethical obligation. Both the
renunciation and the verb suggest the possibility that the postwar era might be
conducive to reformulating “well-being” in ways that, as in Pride
and Prejudice, tie affective responsiveness to practical reason, repudiating
the kinds of rapacious conatus that
characterize the Nazi calamity, with its totalitarian combination of direct and
indirect violence. However, Grass depicts such hopes as delusional. The postwar
“economic miracle” returns rapacious conatus to the more “prudent” indirect coercion of capitalism,
while postwar artistic, cultural liberation serves narcissistic, appropriative,
consumerist desires.18 Renouncing drumming simply leads Oskar to
invest more in an obsessive pursuit of the women—Maria, nurses, and
nuns—whom he associates with his mother and grandmother. Like those of his
fellow citizens, Oskar’s activities mirror fascistic yearnings to consume and
to be fed by others, which in turn mirrors in the frantic postwar pursuit of
material well-being, as though an “economic miracle” could assuage inner
hunger and deaden guilt. Widespread capitalizing upon anti-human art likewise
feeds upon the psychic trauma of Nazism.10 An artist, notably nicknamed Raskolnikov, who treats his
models as instruments and paints Oskar as an epitome of deformity, urges him to
return to his drum. When Oskar protests, “All that is ended,” Raskolnikov
replies, “Nothing is ended, everything returns . . .’ (473/392). This
Raskolnikov, unlike Dostoyevsky’s, denies that affective responsiveness might
reform practical reason enough to allow gradual, narrative progress, and makes
that denial the cornerstone of both his private tyrannizing and his
remunerative, emotionally indulgent art.
Oskar
becomes a celebrity through resuming drumming in ways that induce infantile
regression in others. He meets the needs of customers of the “Onion Cellar,”
who artificially induce tears so that sentimental, self-important fine feelings
can distance them from any real pangs of guilt over their pre-1945 activities.
Notably his drumming, lionized by the postwar public, replicates the
psychological effects of Hitler’s speechifying (see Arker 1989: 151-61).
Similarly, his pathological pursuit of Sister Dorothea suggests, in its
cartoonish exaggeration of Marcel’s drive to “know” Albertine absolutely,
that the capacity to connect with another has been reduced to the compulsion to
assimilate another into one’s own walled-off, “embryonic” identity.
Emotional identification with the “happiness” whose pursuit, Hogan suggests,
structures prototypic narratives universally becomes impossible. In the place of
affective, discursive interaction with others, Oskar revels in possessing Sister
Dorothea’s severed finger, which he places in a preserving jar. When the
police seek him on suspicion of murder, he notes, "Political obstacles, the
so-called Iron Curtain, forbade me to flee eastward. It was not possible to head
for my grandmother['s] . . . four skirts, . . . although I told myself that if
flight there must be, my grandmother's skirts were the only worthwhile ["aussichtsreiche"]
destination" (577/482).
Oskar’s story announces the liquidation of the kind of subjectivity novelistic discourse was designed to delineate. In the place of pre-modern tragedy, the promise of “healthy” affective-cognitive integration and thus narrative agency as depicted by Austen and Dostoyevsky vanishes before the alternatives of two forms of stasis or atrophy—either the collapse of “narrative structures” eliciting empathetic identification into grim accounts of a rapacious conatus, increasingly divorced from all practical reason, or nightmarishly futile attempts to evade incorporation into either such a conatus or the frivolous, faddish freedoms of postmodern societies. This futility is depicted in The Tin Drum by Oskar’s increasing dread that the Black Witch, a malevolent persona from fairy tales suggesting death, meaninglessness, and blind materiality, is after him, is about to absorb him just as he cannot but long to absorb those he “loves” (577-89/482-91). While somatic marking remains integral to any cognitive processing not marked by biological “brain damage,” it appears so thoroughly blocked from reformative dialogue with extended consciousness that the present of the novel offers neither individuals nor societies much hope of a future that could be identified with what Damasio terms “wellness or well-being” (2003: 35).
Notes
1.
Anthony Giddens notes that pre-modern polities have limited means of
surveillance and administrative control (only in "military and religious
settings and slave-labouring in mines and on plantations" does one find
"anything resembling modern administrative power"), for there is
neither territorial integration (clear boundaries, as opposed to vague, shifting
frontiers) nor a vertical integration of classes into one "people":
"Traditional states, especially the larger ones, contained many secondary
settlement frontiers. . . . In conquest empires it was generally the case that
indigenous populations would be left to carry on their pre-existing patterns of
conduct--even their established administrative system being left largely
untouched--so long as they paid their taxes or delivered the necessary
tribute” (1987: 48, 51-52).
2.
"[T]he success of the state in claiming monopoly of the means of violence
was limited by two factors: the manner in which the military was organized, and
the relative slowness of transport and communication. . . . Since it was
impossible in most circumstances for such recruits [ethnically heterogeneous and
paid mostly through booty] to be welded into a 'bureaucratic army', the military
preparation of such soldiery could easily rebound upon those who had instigated
it, by creating potentially independent, rival sources of power within the
state. On the other hand, without the capability of swelling whatever regular
soldiery might exist, the state might either succumb to external attack, or face
the internal decay of its rule” (56-57). Also see Giddens 1981: 49-68, 90-108.
3.
Non-Western traditional literatures, no less than Greek tragedies and Hebraic
prophetic scriptures, depict asocial egotism, deficient affective
responsiveness, and conceptual rigidity as mutually reinforcing and harmful to
practical reasoning (see Jackson 1982: 22-23). The West African Kuranko term hankilimaiye,
like the Yoruba iwa, and the Akan nyansa, has in common with Aristotelian phronêsis and Ciceronian prudentia
a semantically encoded insistence upon the positive relationship between
receptivity to affect and successful exercises of practical reason (see Plutarch,
Moralia 6:34-37). Jackson notes,
"The Kuranko trickster, Hare, uses his superior intelligence to
double-cross and dupe his status superior, Hyena” (92), but cleverness (hankili)
is affirmed only when the hyena abuses hierarchical order to monopolize food or
seek to reduce others to slaves (108). Moreover, conventionality and
authoritarianism is frequently depicted as breeding a “political” stupidity
born of lack of empathy (112).
4.
For the application of this paradigm first to Scotland and then to non-Western
societies, see Phillipson 1997; Carnall 1997; Kidd 1993.
5.
See esp. Warner 1998; Doody 1996:15-32, 274-300; Brown 1996:11-43; Ballaster
1992; Spacks 1990; Todd 1989; Spencer 1986. For contrasting assessments of Eliza
Haywood’s fiction’s relation to the later novel, see Backscheider 2000:
19-47 and Richetti 2000: 240-58.
6.
See Sarah Fielding 1749: 8-9, 11, 12; Darnton 1984: 215-56; Sussman 2000:130-58;
Coventry 1751.
7.
Warner discusses the “absorptive reading” associated with the early
18th-century novels of amorous intrigue (88-127), arguing that such narratives
present “sexualized bodies and amoral egos plotting to secure their own
pleasures at the expense of others,” an “entertainment” whose popularity
“seems to depend upon turning the empty ego of the central protagonist into a
reader’s seat from which readers can follow a blatantly self-interested quest
for victory on the field of amorous conquest” (92). Warner documents how the
appeal of such “entertainment” provoked moral and cultural unease.
8.
See esp. the letters of Clarissa’s mother (L 25. 2, pp. 124-25, L 41.1, pp.
188-90), John Harlowe (L 32.2, p. 150, L 60.1, pp. 253-54, L 62.1, p. 260, L
63.2, p. 267, L 63.4, p. 268, L 402, p. 1192), Anthony Harlow (L 32.4, pp.
154-58), Rev. Brand (L 444, pp. 1292-95. On the significance of the portait of
Rev. Brand, see Weinbrot 1996: 117-40.
9.
On the significance of Austen’s indirect free style for the novel’s generic
evolution, see esp. Wiltshire 2001; Tuite 2002; Galperin 2003.
10.
For the novel in general, see esp. Bender 1987); Armstrong 1987; Armstrong and
Tennenhouse 1989: 1-26; Cottom 1987, 1989, 1991; Miller 1988. For Austen, see
Galperin 2003; Tuite 2002, esp. 1-22; Johnson 2000: 25-44); Rajan 2000: 3-25;
Smith 2000; Galperin 1997: 19-27; Brownstein 1994:180-92; Stewart 1993; Said
1993; Sedgwick 1993; Litvak 1992; Fraiman 1989.
11.
For Austen’s critical relation to contemporary women’s fiction, see Waldron
1999.
12.
See Jones 1990: 79-82; Meerson 1998: 55.
13.
Such “estrangements” are psychological equivalents, and consequences, of the
deracination, or “uprootedness from the soil” (bespochvennost), that Dostoyevsky and other mid-19th
century Russian conservative thinkers attributed to Western secularizing,
scientistic influences, and to the penchant for “theoreticism” on the part
of Westernized Russian intellectuals. See Offord 2002: 111-30; Thompson 2002:
191-211; Bakhtin 1984: 78-100; Mochulsky 1967: 219-35. On the relation of
disgust and estrangement to depressive violence, see Kristeva 1989.
14.
On the relation of this view of the redemptive power of (verbal evoked) mental
images and “incarnational reading” to Dostoyevsky’s religious thought, see
Ziolkowski 2001: 156-70; Ollivier 2001: 51-68; Russell 2001: 226-36; Jones 2002:
148-74.
15.
Striking thematic and structural parallels between The Tin Drum and García Márquez’s One Hundred Years of Solitude (1967) on the one hand and Rushdie’s
Midnight’s Children (1981) on the
other are well delineated by Merivale 1995: 329-345. The battle between
metastasizing all-absorbing Systems and anarchic, subversive, ludic
“counter-forces” structures of Pynchon’s Gravity’s
Rainbow (1973), whose final section is entitled “The Counterforce,” the
ineffectuality of which is underscored by an apocalyptic conclusion. Indeed, all
four novels conclude with apocalypse—the foreclosure of any possible (or
meaningful) future.
16.
See Delaney 2004: 31-32; Rothenberg 1976: 25-26.
17.
See Reddick 1974: 25-29.
18.
See Delaney 2004: 129-41; O’Neill 1999: 26-27; Rothenberg 1976: 18-26.
19.
For the affiliations of Grass’ and Oskar’s art with such an ethically
problematized aesthetics, see Minden 1993: 149-63.
Works
Cited
Arker,
Dieter. Nichts ist vorbei, alles kommt wieder: Untersuchungen zu Günter
Grass’ “Blechtrommel.” Heidelberg: Carl Winter. Universitätsverlag,
1989.
Armstrong,
Nancy. Desire and Domestic Fiction: A
Political History of the Novel. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1987.
Armstrong,
Nancy and Leonard Tennenhouse. "Introduction: Representing violence, or
'how the west was won.'" In The Violence of Representation. Ed. Nancy Armstrong and Leonard
Tennenhouse. New York: Routledge, 1989. 1-26.
Austen,
Jane. Emma. New York: Signet,
1964.
-----. Mansfield Park. Harmondsworth:
Penguin, 1966.
-----. Pride and Prejudice.
Ed. Donald J. Gray. New York: Norton, 1966.
Backscheider,
Paula R. “The Story of Eliza Haywood’s Novels: Caveats and Questions.” In The Passionate
Fictions of Eliza Haywood: Essays on Her Life and Work. Eds. Kirsten T.
Saxon and Rebecca P. Bocchicchio. Lexington: University of Kentucky Press, 2000.
19-47.
Bakhtin,
Mikhail. Problems of Dostoyevsky’s
Poetics. Trans. Caryl Emerson. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press,
1984.
Ballaster,
Ros. Seductive Forms: Women’s Amatory Fiction from 1684 to 1740. New
York: Oxford University Press, 1992.
Belknap,
Robert L. “Dostoevskii and Psychology.”
In The Cambridge Companion to Dostoevskii. Ed. W. J. Leatherbarrow.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002. 131-47.
Bender,
John. Imagining the Penitentiary: Fiction and the Architecture of the Mind in
Eighteenth-Century England. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1987.
Brown,
Homer Obed. “How the Story of the Origin of the (English) Novel is an American
Romance (If Not the Great American Novel).” In Cultural
Institutions of the Novel. Eds. Deidre Lynch and William B. Warner. Durham:
Duke University Press, 1996), 11-43.
Brownstein,
Rachel M. “Irony and Authority.” In
New Casebooks: “Sense and Sensibility” and “Pride and Prejudice”.
Ed. Robert Clark. New York: St. Martin’s Press, 1994. 180-92.
Bucci,
Wilma. Psychoanalysis and Cognitive Science: A Multiple Code Theory. New
York and London: Guilford Press, 1997.
Carnall,
Geoffrey. “Robertson and Comtemporary Images of India.” In William
Robertson and the Expansion of Empire. Ed. Stewart J. Brown. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1997. 210-30.
Cottom,
Daniel. Abyss of Reason: Cultural
Movements, Revelations, and Betrayals. New York: Oxford University Press,
1991.
-----.
Social Figures: George Eliot, Social History, and Literary
Representation. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1987.
-----.
Text and Culture: The Politics of Interpretation. Minneapolis:
University of Minnesota Press, 1989.
Coventry,
Francis. An Essay on the New Species of
Writing Founded by Mr. Fielding. London: W. Owen, 1751. Rpt. in The
Augustan Reprint Society, no. 95 (Los Angeles: Willian Andrews Clark
Memorial Library, Unversity of California Press, 1962.
Damasio,
Antonio. Descartes’ Error: Emotion,
Reason, and the Human Brain. New York: Putnam, 1994.
-----.
The Feeling of What Happens: Body and Emotion in the Making of
Consciousness. New York: Harcourt Brace and Company, 1999.
-----.
Looking for Spinoza: Joy, Sorrow, and the Feeling Brain. Orland:
Harcourt, 2003.
Darnton,
Robert. The Great Cat Massacre and Other
Episodes in French Cultural History. New York: Random House, 1984
Delaney,
Antoinette T. Metaphors in Grass’ Die
Blechtrommel. New York: Peter Lang,
2004.
Diderot,
Denis. Éloge de Richardson. In Denis Diderot, Oeuvres esthétiques. Ed. Paul Vernière. Paris: Classiques Garnier,
1959.
Doody,
Margaret Anne. The True Story of the Novel.
New Brunswick, N. J.: Rutgers University Press,1996.
Dostoyevsky,
Fyodor. Crime and Punishment. Trans.
David McDuff. New York: Penguin, 1991.
-----.
Prestuplenije I Nakazeanije. Mockba: Slavyanka, 1993.
Fielding,
Henry. The History of Tom Jones, A
Foundling. Middletown, Conn: Wesleyan University Press, 1975.
Fielding,
Sarah. Remarks on Clarissa. London:
Robinson, 1749. Rpt. in The Augustan
Reprint Society, no. 231-232 (Los Angeles: William Andrews Clark Memorial
Library, University of California Press, 1985.
Fraiman,
Susan. “The Humiliation of Elizabeth Bennet.”
In Refiguring the Father: New
Feminist Readings of Patriarchy. Eds. Patricia Yaeger and Beth
Kowalski-Wallace. Cardondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1989. 168-87.
Galperin,
William H. The Historical Austen.
Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 2003.
-----.
“The Picturesque, the Real, and the Consumption of Jane Austen.” Wordsworth
Circle 28.1 (Winter 1997):
19-27.
Giddens,
Anthony. A Contemporary Critique of
Historical Materialism. Vol. 1: Power,
Property, and the State. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1981.
-----.
The Nation-State and Violence. Vol. 2 of A Contemporary Critique of Historical Materialism. Berkeley:
University of California Press, 1987.
Grass,
Günter. Die Blechtrommel. Danziger Trilogie 1. Darmstadt und Neuwied:
Luchterhand, 1974 [1959].
-----.
The Tin Drum. New York: Vintage, 1961, 1962.
Hogan,
Patrick Colm. Cognitive Science,
Literature, and the Arts: A Guide for Humanists. New York and London:
Routledge, 2003.
-----.
The Mind and its Stories: Narrative Universals and Human Emotion.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003.
Jackson,
Michael. Allegories of the Wilderness:
Ethics and Ambiguity in Kuranko Narrative. Bloomington: Indiana University
Press, 1982.
Johnson,
Claudia L. “The Divine Miss Jane: Jane Austen, Janeites, and the Discipline of
Novel Studies.” In Janeities: Austen’s
Disciples and Devotees. Ed. Deidre Lynch. Princeton and Oxford: Princeton
University Press, 2000. 25-44.
Jones,
Malcolm V. Dostoyevsky After Bakhtin:
Readings in Dostoyevsky’s Fantastic Realism. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1990.
-----.
“Dostoevskii and Religion.” In The
Cambridge Companion to Dostoeskii. Ed. W. J. Leatherbarrow. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 2002. 148-74.
Kidd,
Colin. Subverting Scotland's Past: Scottish Whig Historians and the Creation of
an Anglo-British Identity, 1689-c. 1830. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1993.
Kristeva,
Julia. Black Sun: Depression and
Melancholia. Trans. Leon S. Roudiez. New York: Columbia University Press,
1989.
LeDoux,
Joseph. Synaptic Self: How Our Brains Become Who We Are. New York: Viking,
2003.
Livak,
Joseph. “Delicacy and Disgust, Mourning and Melancholia, Privilege and
Perversity. Pride and Prejudice.” Qui
Parle 6.1 (1992): 35-51.
Meerson,
Olga. Dostoevsky’s Taboos. Dresden-München: Dresden University Press,
1998.
Merivale,
Patricia. “Saleem Fathered by Oskar: Midnight’s
Children, Magical Realiss, and The Tin
Drum.” In Magical Realism: Theory,
History, Community. Ed. Lois Parkinson Zamora and Wendy B. Faris. Durham and
London: Duke University Press, 1995. 329-45.
Miller,
D. A. The Novel and the Police. Berkeley: University of California Press,
1988.
Minden,
Michael. “A Post-Realist Aesthetic: Günter Grass, Die
Blechtrommel.” In The
German Novel in the Twentieth Century: Beyond Realism. Ed. David Mingley.
Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press/New York: St. Martin’s Press, 1993.
149-163.
Mochulsky,
Konstantin. Dostoyevsky: His Life and Work.
Trans. Michael A. Minihan. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1967.
Nussbaum,
Martha C. Upheavals of Thought: The
Intelligence of Emotions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001.
Oatley,
Keith and P. N. Johnson-Laird. “Toward a Cognitive Theory of the Emotions.” Cognition
and Emotions 1.1 (1987): 29-50.
Offord,
Derek. “Dostoeskii and the Intelligentsia.”
In The Cambridge Companion to
Dostoevskii. Ed. W. J. Leatherbarrow. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
2002. 111-30.
Ollivier,
Sophie. “Icons in Dostoevsky’s Works.”
In Dostoevsky and the Christian
Tradition. Ed. George Pattison and Diane Oening Thompson. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 2001. 51-68.
O’Neill,
Patrick. Günter Grass Revisited. New
York: Twayne, 1999.
Phillipson,
Nicholas. "Providence and Progress: An Introduction to the Historical
Thought of William Robertson." In William
Robertson and the Expansion of Empire. Ed. Stewart J. Brown. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1997. 55-73.
Plutarch,
"On Moral Virtue." In Moralia.
Vol. 6. Trans. W. C. Hembold. Cambridge: Loeb Classical Library, 1939.
Rajan,
Rajewari Sunder. “Austen in the World: Postcolonial Mappings.” In The
Postcolonial Jane Austen. Ed. You-me Park and Rajeswari Sunder Rajan. London
and New York: Routledge, 2000. 3-25.
Reddick,
John. The “Danzig Triology” of Günter Grass: A Study of The Tin Drum, Cat
and Mouse, and Dog Years. New York and London: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich,
1974.
Richardson,
Samuel. Clarissa, or The History of a
Young Lady. Ed. Angus Ross. New York: Penguin, 1985.
Richetti,
John. “Histories of Eliza Haywood and Henry Fielding: Imitation and
Adaptation,” In
The Passionate Fictions of Eliza Haywood: Essays on Her Life and Work. Eds.
Kirsten T. Saxon and Rebecca P. Bocchicchio. Lexington: University of Kentucky
Press, 2000. 240-58.
Rothenberg,
Jürgen. Günter Grass: Das Chaos in
verbesserter Ausführung: Zeitgeschichte als Thema und Aufgabe des Prosawerks.
Heidelberg: Carl Winter. Unversitätsverlag, 1976.
Russell,
Henry M. W. “Beyond the Will: Humiliation as Christian Necessity in Crime
and Punishment.” In Dostoevsky and
the Christian Tradition. Ed. George Pattison and Diane Oening Thompson.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001. 226-36.
Said,
Edward W. Culture and Imperialism. New York: Knopf, 1993.
Scheub,
Harold. Story. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 1998.
Sedgwick,
Eve Kosofsky, “Jane Austen and the Masturbating Girl.” In Eve Kosofsky
Sedgwick, Tendencies. Durham: Duke University Press, 1993.
Smith,
Johanna M. “The Opposition Reader and Pride
and Prejudice.” In A
Companion to Jane Austen Studies. Eds. Laura Cooner Lambdin and Robert
Thomas Lambdin. Westport, Conn.: Greenwood, 2000.
Spacks,
Patricia Meyer. Desire and Truth:
Functions of Plot in Eighteenth-Century English Novels. Chicago: University
of Chicago Press, 1990.
Spencer,
Jane, The Rise of the Woman Novelist; From Aphra Behn to Jane Austen, Oxford:
Basil Blackwell, 1986.
Stewart,
Maaja. Domestic Realities and Imperial Fictions: Jane Austen’s Novels in
Eighteenth-Century Contexts. Athens: University of Georgia Press, 1993.
Sussman,
Charlotte. Consuming Anxieties: Consumer
Protest, Gender, and British Slavery, 1713-1833. Stanford: Stanford
University Press, 2000.
Thompson,
Diane Oenning. “Dostoevskii and Science.”
In The Cambridge Companion to
Dostoevskii. Ed. W. J. Leatherbarrow. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
2001. 191-211.
Todd,
Janet. The Sign of Angelica: Women, Writing, and Fiction, 1660-1800. New
York: Columbia University Press, 1989.
Tuite,
Clara. Romantic Austen: Sexual Politics and the Canon. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2002.
Waldron,
Mary. Jane Austen and the Fiction of Her Time. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1999.
Warner,
William B. Licensing Entertainment: The
Elevation of Novel Reading in Britain, 1684-1750.
Berkeley: University of California Press, 1998.
Weinbrot,
Howard D. “Clarissa, Elias Brand and
Death by Parentheses.” In New Essays on Samuel Richardson. 1996.117-40
Wiltshire,
John. Recreating Jane Austen.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001.
Ziolkowiski,
Eric J. “Reading and Incarnation in Dostoevsky.”
In Dostoevsky and the Christian
Tradition. Ed. George Pattison and Diane Oening Thompson. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 2001. 156-70.